REVIEWS
43
structions, can be regarded as a kind of Turing machine. It is thus immediately clear that computa-
bility, so defined, can be identified with (especially, is no less general than) the notion of effectiveness
as it appears in certain mathematical problems (various forms of the Entscheidungsproblem, various
problems to find complete sets of invariants in topology, group theory, etc., and in general any prob-
lem which concerns the discovery of an algorithm).
The principal result is that there exist sequences (well-defined on classical grounds) which are
not computable. In particular the deducibility problem of the functional calculus of first order (Hilbert
and Ackermann's engere Funktionenkalkiil) is unsolvable in the sense that, if the formulas of this
calculus are enumerated in a straightforward manner, the sequence whose nth term is 0 or 1, according
as the nth formula in the enumeration is or is not deducible, is not computable. (The proof here re-
quires some correction in matters of detail.)
In an appendix the author sketches a proof of equivalence of "computability" in his sense and
"effective calculability" in the sense of the present reviewer {American journal of mathematics,
vol.
58 (1936), pp. 345-363, see review in this
JOURNAL,
vol. 1, pp. 73-74). The author's result con-
cerning the existence of uncomputable sequences was also anticipated, in terms of effective calcula-
bility, in the cited paper. His work was, however, done independently, being nearly complete and
known in substance to a number of persons at the time that the paper appeared.
As a matter of fact, there is involved here the equivalence of three different notions: computa-
bility by a Turing machine, general recursiveness in the sense of Herbrand-Godel-Kleene, and X-de-
finability in the sense of Kleene and the present reviewer. Of these, the first has the advantage of
making the identification with effectiveness in the ordinary (not explicitly defined) sense evident
immediately—i.e. without the necessity of proving preliminary theorems. The second and third
have the advantage of suitability for embodiment in a system of symbolic logic.
ALONZO CHURCH
EMILL. POST.
Finite combinatory processes—formulation 1. The journal of symbolic logic, vol.
1(1936), pp. 103-105.
The author proposes a definition of "finite 1-process" which is similar in formulation, and in
fact equivalent, to computation by a Turing machine (see the preceding review). He does not, how-
ever, regard his formulation as certainly to be identified with effectiveness in the ordinary sense,
but takes this identification as a "working hypothesis" in need of continual verification. To this the
reviewer would object that effectiveness in the ordinary sense has not been given an exact definition,
and hence the working hypothesis in question has not an exact meaning. To define effectiveness as
computability by an arbitrary machine, subject to restrictions of finiteness, would seem to be an
adequate representation of the ordinary notion, and if this is done the need for a working hypothesis
disappears.
The present paper was written independently of Turing's, which was at the time in press but
had not yet
appeared.
ALONZO CHURCH
H. B. SiiiTH. The
algebra
of propositions. Philosophy of science, vol. 3 (1936), pp. 551-578.
The author is proposing a calculus of propositions based on four primitive ideas: disjunction
p+q,
conjunction pq, negation p', and implication p£q. Although not explicitly stated, it is appar-
ently intended that the first three operations shall obey all the usual laws. The implication p L
q
is not,
however, to be identified with p'+q, and is thus in some degree analogous to C. I. Lewis's p-iq. A
modal operation \p\, analogous to Lewis's Qp, is defined as (p
/.0)',
where 0 is the null-proposition
(a proposition q such that
q/.q').
Equivalence is expressed by p =
q,
apparently to be defined as
(P£q){qlp).
On intuitive grounds not entirely clear, the author requires that "all modal distinctions" shall
be recognized. That is, let two expressions be formed from the letter p, each by a finite number of
applications of negation and the modal operation, negation being nowhere applied twice in succession
(i.e.
without one or more intervening applications of the modal operation); then these two expressions
shall not be assumed equivalent unless they are identical expressions.
An immediate difficulty is that if we assume (1)
p/-\\p\
'| 'and (2) (p £q)(q £r) Z(p Zr) and the
principle of inference (3), "If P and PQ Z R then QIR," then it is possible to infer \p\'=•=
111
p\ '\ '\'.
This the author meets by rejecting (2). (In connection with an earlier note on this same point, the