Cellular automata in operational probabilistic theories
Paolo Perinotti
QUIT Group, Dipartimento di Fisica, Università degli studi di Pavia, and INFN sezione di Pavia, via Bassi 6, 27100 Pavia, Italy
The theory of cellular automata in oper-
ational probabilistic theories is developed.
We start introducing the composition of
infinitely many elementary systems, and
then use this notion to define update rules
for such infinite composite systems. The
notion of causal influence is introduced,
and its relation with the usual property of
signalling is discussed. We then introduce
homogeneity, namely the property of an
update rule to evolve every system in the
same way, and prove that systems evolving
by a homogeneous rule always correspond
to vertices of a Cayley graph. Next, we de-
fine the notion of locality for update rules.
Cellular automata are then defined as ho-
mogeneous and local update rules. Finally,
we prove a general version of the wrapping
lemma, that connects CA on different Cay-
ley graphs sharing some small-scale struc-
ture of neighbourhoods.
Contents
1 Introduction 1
2 Detailed outlook 3
3 Operational Probabilistic Theories 4
3.1 Formal framework . . . . . . . . . 5
3.2 Causality and the no-restriction
hypothesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
3.3 Norms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10
4 The quasi-local algebra in OPTs 13
4.1 Quasi-local effects . . . . . . . . . . 13
4.2 Extended states . . . . . . . . . . . 19
4.3 Quasi-local transformations . . . . 22
5 Global update rules 30
5.1 Update rule . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31
5.2 Admissibility and local action . . . 34
Paolo Perinotti: paolo.perinotti@unipv.it,
http://www.qubit.it
5.3 Causal influence . . . . . . . . . . . 36
5.3.1 Relation with signalling . . 38
5.4 Block decomposition . . . . . . . . 38
6 Homogeneity 40
7 Locality 47
8 Cellular Automata 50
8.1 Results . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
9 Examples 54
9.1 Classical case . . . . . . . . . . . . 54
9.2 Quantum case . . . . . . . . . . . . 55
9.3 Fermionic case . . . . . . . . . . . 55
10 Conclusion 56
Acknowledgments 56
A Identification of the sup- and opera-
tional norm for effects 56
B Quasi-local states 57
C Proof of identity 94 63
D Homogeneity and causal influence 64
E Proof of right and left invertibility of
a locally defined GUR 64
F Proof of theorem 10 65
G Proof of lemmas 66 and 67 66
References 67
1 Introduction
In the last two decades a new approach to quan-
tum foundations arose, grounded on the quan-
tum information experience [1, 2, 3, 4]. This line
of research on the fundamental aspects of quan-
tum theory benefits from new ideas, concepts and
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 1
arXiv:1911.11216v3 [quant-ph] 6 Jul 2020
methods [5, 6, 7] that lead to a wealth of remark-
able results [8, 9, 10, 11]. In particular, quan-
tum theory can be now understood as a theory
of information processing, that is selected among
a universe of alternate theories [12, 13, 1, 14] by
operational principles about the possibility or im-
possibility to perform specific information pro-
cessing tasks [9, 15].
The scenario of alternate theories among which
the principles select quantum theory is called the
framework of Operational Probabilistic Theories
(OPTs) [8, 15], and has connections with the less
structured concept of Generalized Probabilistic
Theory (GPT) [5, 16, 17], as well as the dia-
grammatic category theoretical approach often
referred to as quantum picturialism [18, 19]. In-
spiration for the framework came also from quan-
tum logic [20, 21].
Quantum theory, namely the theory of Hilbert
spaces, density matrices, completely positive
maps and POVMs (in particular we refer to the
elegant exposition of Ref. [22]), can thus be re-
formulated as a special theory of information pro-
cessing. Besides the many advantages of this re-
sult, one has to face a main issue: the theory
as such is devoid of its physical content. El-
ementary systems are thought of as elementary
information carriers—brutally speaking, memory
cells—rather than elementary particles or fields in
space-time. While this framework is satisfactory
for an effective, empirical description of physical
experiments, when it comes to provide a theo-
retical foundation for the physics of elementary
systems, the informational approach at this stage
calls for a way to re-embrace mechanical notions
such as mass, energy, position, space-time, and
complete the picture encompassing the dynamics
of quantum systems.
A recent proposal for this endeavour is based
on the idea that physical laws have to be ulti-
mately understood as algorithms, that make sys-
tems evolve, changing their state, exactly as the
memory cells of a computer are updated by the
run of an algorithm [23, 24, 25]. Such a program
already achieved successful results in the recon-
struction of Weyl’s, Dirac’s and Maxwell’s equa-
tions (for a comprehensive review see Ref. [26]).
The most natural candidate algorithm for de-
scribing a physical law in this context is a cellular
automaton. The theory of cellular automata is
a wide and established branch of computer sci-
ence. The notion of a cellular automaton for
quantum systems was first devised as the quan-
tum version of its classical counterpart, e.g. in
Refs. [27, 28, 29, 30], but turned out to give rise to
a rather independent theory, developed starting
from Ref. [31]: the theory of Quantum Cellular
Automata (QCAs). The latter counts presently
various important results—see e.g. Refs. [32, 33],
just to mention a few. We stress that, most
commonly, QCAs are defined to be reversible al-
gorithms, and most results in the literature are
proved with this hypothesis. It is known, how-
ever, that many desirable preoperties fail to hold
in the irreversible case (see e.g. Ref. [34]). In the
present work we will not consider irreversible cel-
lular automata, and leave this subject for further
studies.
In order to use cellular automata as candi-
date physical laws in the foundational perspec-
tive based on OPTs, one has two choices at
hand. The first one is to start treating automata
within a definite theory, and this is the approach
adopted so far, in particular within Fermionic
theory [35, 36, 37]. In the linear case, Fermionic
cellular automata reduce to Quantum Walks, and
this brings in the picture all the tools from such
widely studied topic [38, 39, 40, 41, 42, 43]. The
non-linear case is far less studied [44, 45], and
does not offer as many results for the analy-
sis. Needless to say, this approach faces difficul-
ties that are specific of the theory at hand, and
prevents a comparison of different theories on a
ground that is genuinely physical.
The second approach is initiated in the present
paper, and consists in defining cellular automata
in the general context of OPTs. This perspective
offers the possibility of extracting the essential
features of the theory of quantum or Fermionic
cellular automata, those that are not specific of
the theory but are well suited in any theory of
information processing. As a consequence, one
can generalise some results, and figure out why
and how others fail to extend to the broader sce-
nario. Moving a much less structured mathemat-
ical context, this approach can use only few tools,
but provides results that have the widest appli-
cability range.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 2
2 Detailed outlook
In this section we provide a short, non technical
discussion of the main results. The purpose of
this work is to define cellular automata in OPTs,
and prove some general results that will help ap-
plying the theory to special cases of interest.
A cellular automaton is an algorithm that up-
dates the information stored in an array of mem-
ory cells in discrete steps, in such a way that one
needs to read the content of a few neighbouring
cells to determine the state of a given cell at the
next step. Cellular automata in the literature
are often, but not always, defined to be homoge-
neous: in this case the local rule for the update
of the cell is the same for every cell. Here we
will adopt homogeneity, but the subject is pre-
sented so that the generalisation of definitions to
inhomogeneous CA is straightforward.
Typically, the interesting case of a cellular au-
tomaton is the one involving an infinite memory
array. The first challenge we have to face is then
to extend the theory of OPTs from finite, arbi-
trarily large composite systems to actually infi-
nite ones. This piece of theory has an interest
per se, for many reasons ranging from the possi-
bility to introduce thermodynamic limits to the
extension of the theory of C
and von Neumann
algebras.
We then start with a review of the framework
of OPTs, and build the necessary tools to define
infinite composite systems. The starting point
is the construction of mathematical objects that
describe measurements on finitely many systems
within an infinite array— the OPT counterpart
of the space of local effects of quantum theory.
Effects for the infinite system are then defined as
limits of Cauchy sequences of local effects. Since
the introduction of a suitable topology for the def-
inition of limits is needed, we open the paper with
section 3, where a review of OPTs is provided,
along with a few new results that will be useful,
and a rather consistent part of the section will be
dedicated to the introduction and discussion of
norms that will provide the necessary topological
framework for a consistent definition of limits.
The subject of the subsequent Section 4 is then
the construction of the Banach space of effects for
the infinite composite system, and consequently
the construction of the space of states as suitable
linear functionals on effects. An important sub-
section will be dedicated to the construction of
the algebra of quasi-local transformations, that
allows for the description of transformations on
an infinite system that can be arbitrarily well ap-
proximated by local operations on finitely many
subsystems. Indeed, an important part of the
theory of CAs in OPTs is built by ruling the way
in which quasi-local transformations are trans-
formed by the CA. In particular, the way in which
the CA propagates the effects of a local transfor-
mation on surrounding subsystems will be the key
to the definition of the neighbourhood of the sub-
system, a concept that is central to the theory of
CAs.
Once this is done, the next step consists in
defining update rules, and their admissibility con-
ditions, which are the subject of Section 5, along
with causal influence and a block-decomposition
theorem. Update rules are defined in the first
place as automorphisms V of the space of quasi-
local effects, but an important request they must
abide is that when they act on a quasi-local trans-
formation A by conjugation as V A V
1
, the ob-
tained transformation is again quasi-local.
The next step is taken in section 6, and con-
sists in defining the property of homogeneity. The
latter presents with some difficulties, stemming
from the fact that, as we mentioned above, we
are defining update rules prior to any mechanical
notion. This implies that even space-time is not
available at this fundamental stage, and without
geometry we cannot define homogeneity as trans-
lational invariance under the group correspond-
ing to a given space-time. On the contrary, we
will define homogeneity by formalising the idea
that every single cell has to be treated equally
by the update rule, and this notion will be de-
fined operationally, requiring that no experiment
made of local operations will allow establishing
any difference between cells. As a consequence
of homogeneity, one can prove that every homo-
geneous update rule is underpinned by the Cay-
ley graph of some group, generalising a result of
Refs. [25, 46]. The mathematical theory known as
geometric group theory then tells us that the Cay-
ley graph representing the causal connections of
cells in the memory array, being a metric space,
uniquely identifies an equivalence class of met-
ric spaces, that captures both the algebraic and
geometric essential features of the group. Aston-
ishingly, for Cayley graphs of finitely presented
groups—which is the case for cellular automata
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 3
as we define them here—the equivalence class al-
ways contains a smooth manifold of dimension at
most four (see Ref. [47], pag. 90). This result
means that we can always think of a cellular au-
tomaton as if it was embedded in a Riemannian
manifold, in such a way that the Riemannian dis-
tance between nodes is almost the same as the
distance between nodes given in terms of steps
along the graph edges.
Also the notion of locality, presented in sec-
tion 7, comes with its own difficulties, that can be
overcome by proving a generalisation of the result
known as “unitarity plus causality implies local-
izability" [32]. This is where the theory, which is
inspired by that of QCAs, deeply differs from the
theory of classical cellular automata. In particu-
lar, considering the collection of transformations
V A V
1
for all A acting on a given system g, we
will define the neighbourhood of g as the set of
systems on which transformations V A V
1
act
non trivially.
Once the theory of cellular automata is fully
developed, some results are proved in Section 8.
In particular, a very useful theorem is the wrap-
ping lemma, which under very wide hypotheses—
though not universal—allows for the classification
of automata on a given infinite graph by classi-
fying automata on any suitably “wrapped" finite
version of the same graph.
In Section 9, a few examples are reviewed. In
particular, using the general notion of locality,
we apply the definition of causal influence and
the neighbourhood scheme to the case of classical
cellular automata. With the above definitions at
hand, we show that allegedly local automata are
actually non-local. This solves a long standing
puzzle about the connection between classical and
quantum automata—the so-called quantisation of
classical automata [31, 48].
The paper is concluded by Section 10 with a
summary of the results and some closing remarks.
3 Operational Probabilistic Theories
In this section we will provide a thorough intro-
duction to OPTs, which is partly a review of the
literature, and partly presentation of new results
that will be used in the remainder. We provide
here a sketchy introduction before going through
formal definitions, and use Quantum Theory as
an illustrative example for the main notions in
the framework.
Quantum theory is about system types A
1
—namely complex Hilbert spaces H
A
that are
classified by their dimension d
A
= dim(H
A
)—and
transformations that can occur on systems as a
consequence of undergoing a test. Tests are rep-
resented by quantum instruments E
X
= {E
i
}
iX
,
i.e. a collection of Completely Positive (CP) maps
E
i
that sum to a trace-preserving one (a channel):
E =
P
iX
E
i
. The quantum operation E
i
—a CP
trace non-increasing map—represents the change
in the system occurring upon the event of a spe-
cific outcome i X in the test. In the diagram-
matic language of OPTs systems are represented
as labelled wires, and instruments or quantum op-
erations as boxes with an input and output wire,
e.g.
A
E
X
B
,
A
E
i
B
,
respecitvely. States can be considered as special
transformations where the input system is I, hav-
ing H
I
= C, i.e. d
I
= 1. Notice that the a prepa-
ration test, i.e. the most general test from I to A,
represents a probabilistic preparation procedure
where some state in the collection P
X
= {ρ
i
}
iX
is prepared, with the sub-normalised density ma-
trix ρ
i
occurring upon reading the outcome i X.
The probability of occurrence of ρ
i
is Tr[ρ
i
], and
ρ =
P
iX
ρ
i
has unit trace. Preparation tests
or states for system A are represented by special
diagrams
P
X
A
,
ρ
i
A
,
respectively. The space H
A
of Hermitian opera-
tors on H
A
, whose dimension is D
A
= d
2
A
, is the
real span of states of system A.
A POVM Q
Y
= {Q
j
}
jY
is a collection of ef-
fects 0 Q
j
I
A
that sum to the identity opera-
tor:
P
jY
Q
j
= I
A
. This kind of test can be seen
as a quantum instrument from A to I, namely a
collection of linear functionals on the real space
spanned by density matrices, where the function-
als a
j
(ρ) are defined as a
j
(ρ)
:
= Tr[ρQ
j
]. The
1
We remark that for the purpose of information pro-
cessing the type of a system is captured by the dimension
of the corresponding Hilbert space, e.g. the electron spin
is of the same type as the photon polarisation. This is
slightly different than the usual notion of system type in
physics, where the two types in the above example are
different.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 4
diagrammatic representation of POVMs and ef-
fects is the following
A
Q
Y
,
A
Q
j
,
respectively.
Composite systems, such as AB, correspond to
to the Hilbert space H
A
H
B
of dimension d
AB
=
d
A
d
B
. Tests {E
i
}
iX
from A to B and {F
j
}
jY
from B to C can be run in sequence, obtaining a
new test: {D
ij
}
(i,j)X×Y
where D
ij
:
= F
j
E
i
. On
the other hand, tests {E
i
}
iX
from A to B and
{E
j
}
jY
from B to B
0
on subsystems of a compos-
ite system AA
0
can be run in parallel, obtaining
the test {D
ij
}
(i,j)X×Y
with D
ij
:
= E
i
F
j
. In
diagrams, we draw for quantum operations
A
F
j
E
i
C
=
A
E
i
B
F
j
C
,
AA
0
E
i
F
j
BB
0
=
A
E
i
B
A
0
F
j
B
0
,
and analogously for instruments.
Very relevant structures in the theory are the
real space H
A
of Hermitian operators on H
A
,
spanned by quantum states, the cone of positive
operators in P
A
H
A
, the convex set of states
[[A]], obtained by intersecting the positive cone
with the half-space Tr[X] 1, and the convex
set of deterministic states [[A]]
1
, obtained by in-
tersecting the positive cone with the affine hy-
perplane Tr[X] = 1. Similar structures can be
generalised to the space spanned by quantum op-
erations. In the general framework of OPTs, we
will systematically refer to the generalisation of
the above concepts.
3.1 Formal framework
The framework of OPTs is meant to capture the
main traits of Quantum Theory (shared e.g. by
Classical Theory, or Fermionic Theory, etc.) sum-
marised above, and use them as defining proper-
ties of a family of abstract theories that might
be candidates for an alternative representation of
elementary physical systems and their transfor-
mations. In the remainder of this section we pro-
vide a brief review of the framework of OPTs (for
reference see e.g. [15, 8, 9]). Some of the most
relevant differences with respect to the quantum
case stem from the fact that systems might not
compose with the tensor product rule.
We warn the reader that this presentation has
some elements that are slightly different from
other reviews in the literature, and is tailored
to ease the presentation of subsequent material.
Most of the results in the present sections are
new, and their proof will be given. Those the-
orems that are not original are not proved, and
due reference is provided.
An operational theory Θ consists in i) a col-
lection Test(Θ) of tests T
AB
X
, each labelled by
input and output letters from a collection Sys(Θ)
denoting system types, e.g. A B—that will
be systematically omitted—and by a finite set of
outcomes X; for every pair of types A, B Sys(Θ)
the set of tests of type A B is denoted hhA
Bii; ii) a very basic associative rule for sequential
composition: the test T
X
hhA Bii can be fol-
lowed by the test S
Y
hhA
0
B
0
ii if A
0
B, thus
obtaining the sequential composition ST
X×Y
hhA B
0
ii; iii) a rule : (A, B) 7→ AB for com-
posing labels in parallel, and a corresponding rule
for tests : (S
X
, T
Y
) 7→ (S T)
X×Y
, with the fol-
lowing properties
1. Associativity: (AB)C = A(BC).
2. For every S
X
hhA Bii and T
Y
hhC
Dii, one has S
X
T
Y
hhAC BDii. Asso-
ciativity of holds:
(S
X
T
Y
) W
Z
= S
X
(T
Y
W
Z
).
3. Unit: there is a label I such that IA = AI =
A for every A Sys(Θ).
4. Identity: for every A Sys(Θ), a test I
A
hhA Aii such that I
B
S
X
= S
X
I
A
= S
X
, for
every S
X
hhA Bii.
5. For every A
X
hhA Bii, B
Y
hhB Cii,
D
Z
hhD Eii, E
W
hhE Fii, one has
(B
Y
E
W
)(A
X
D
Z
) = (B
Y
A
X
) (E
W
D
Z
).
(1)
6. Braiding: for every pair of system types A, B,
there exist tests S
AB
, S
AB
hhAB BAii
such that S
BA
S
AB
= S
BA
S
AB
= I
AB
, and
S
AB
(A
X
B
Y
) = (B
Y
A
X
)S
AB
. Moreover,
S
(AB)C
= (I
A
S
BC
)(S
AC
I
B
),
S
A(BC)
= (S
AB
I
C
)(I
B
S
AC
).
When S
AB
S
AB
, the theory is symmetric.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 5
All the theories developed so far are symmetric.
All tests of an operational theory are (finite)
collections of events: hhA Bii 3 R
X
= {R
i
}
iX
.
If hhA Bii 3 R
X
= {R
i
}
iX
and hhB Cii 3
T
Y
= {T
j
}
jY
, then
hhA Cii 3 (TR)
X×Y
:
= {T
j
R
i
}
(i,j)X×Y
.
Similarly, for R
X
hhA Bii and T
Y
hhC
Dii,
(R T)
X×Y
:
= {R
i
T
j
}
(i,j)X×Y
.
The set of events of tests in hhA Bii is de-
noted by [[A B]]. By the properties of se-
quential and parallel composition of tests, one
can easily derive associativity of sequential and
parallel composition of events, as well as the ana-
logue of Eq. (1). For every test T
X
hhA Bii
with T
X
= {T
i
}
iX
, and every disjoint partition
{X
j
}
jY
of X =
S
jY
X
j
, one has a coarse grain-
ing operation that maps T
X
to T
0
Y
hhA Bii,
with T
0
Y
= {T
0
j
}
jY
. We define T
X
j
:
= T
0
j
. The
parallel and sequential compositions distribute
over coarse graining:
T
X
j
R
k
= (T R)
X
j
×{k}
,
A
l
T
X
j
B
k
= (A T B)
{lX
j
×{k}
.
Notice that for every test T
X
hhA Bii there
exists the singleton test T
0
:
= {T
X
}. One can
easily prove that the identity test I
A
is a sin-
gleton: I
A
= {I
A
}, and I
B
T = T I
A
for
every event T [[A B]]. Similarly, for
S
AB
= {S
AB
} and S
AB
= {S
AB
} we have
S
BA
S
AB
= S
BA
S
AB
= I
AB
. The collection of
events of an operational theory Θ will be denoted
by Ev(Θ). The above requirements make the col-
lections Test(Θ) and Ev(Θ) the families of mor-
phisms of two braided monoidal categories with
the same objects—system types Sys(Θ).
An operational theory is an OPT if the tests
hhI Iii are probability distributions: 1 T
i
=
p
i
0, so that
P
iX
p
i
= 1, and given two tests
S
X
, T
Y
hhI Iii with S
i
= p
i
and T
i
= q
i
, the
following identities hold
S
i
T
j
= S
i
T
j
:
= p
i
q
j
,
T
X
j
:
=
X
iX
j
p
i
,
meaning that events in the same test are mutually
exclusive and events in different tests of system I
are independent. While it is immediate that 1
[[I I]]—since {1}
= {I
I
} is the only singleton
test—we will assume that 0 [[I I]]. This
means that we can consider e.g. tests of the form
{1, 0, 0}.
Events in [[A B]] are called transformations.
As a consequence of the above definitions, every
set [[A]]
:
= [[I A]] can be viewed as a set of
functionals on [[
¯
A]]. As such, it can be viewed as
a spanning subset of the real vector space [[A]]
R
of linear funcitonals on [[
¯
A]]. On the other hand
[[
¯
A]]
:
= [[A I]] is a separating set of positive
linear functionals on [[A]], which then spans the
dual space [[A]]
R
=: [[
¯
A]]
R
. The dimension D
A
of
[[A]]
R
(which is the same as that of [[
¯
A]]
R
) is called
size of system A. One can easily prove that in
any OPT Θ, I is the unique system with unit size
D
I
= 1. Using the properties of parallel compo-
sition, one can also prove that D
AB
D
A
D
B
.
Events in [[A]] are called states, and denoted by
lower-case greek letters, e.g. ρ, while events in [[
¯
A]]
are called effects, and denoted by lower-case latin
letters, e.g. a. When it is appropriate, we will
use the symbol |ρ) to denote a state, and (a| to
denote an effect. We will also use the circuit no-
tation, where we denote states, transformations
and effects by the symbols
ρ
A
,
A
A
B
,
A
a
,
respectively. Sequential composition of A
[[A B]] and B [[B C]] is denoted by the
diagram
A
BA
C
=
A
A
B
B
C
.
For composite systems we use diagrams with mul-
tiple wires, e.g.
A
A
B
C D
.
The identity will be omitted:
A
I
A
=
A
. The swap S
AB
and its inverse will be de-
noted as follows
A
S
B
B A
=
B
B
A
A
A
S
B
B A
=
B
B
A
A
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 6
In the present paper we will always assume
that the theory under consideration is symmet-
ric, however all the results will be straightfor-
wardly generalisable. We will consequently draw
the swap S
AB
as
A
S
B
B A
=
A
S
B
B A
=
B
B
A
A
An OPT Θ is specified by the collections of
systems and tests, along with the parallel com-
position rule
Θ (Test(Θ), Sys(Θ), ).
Definition 1 (Equal transformations). Let
A , B [[A B]]. Then we define A = B
if for every system C and every ρ [[AC]] and
a [[
¯
B
¯
C]], one has
ρ
A
A
B
a
C
=
ρ
A
B
B
a
C
Notice that, since states separate effects and
viceversa effects separate states, the above defi-
nition is equivalent to the two following equality
criteria.
Lemma 1. Let A , B [[A B]]. Then the
following conditions are equivalent.
1. A = B.
2. For every C and every ρ [[AC]], one has
ρ
A
A
B
C
=
ρ
A
B
B
C
.
(2)
3. For every C and every a [[
¯
B
¯
C]], one has
A
A
B
a
C
=
A
B
B
a
C
.
(3)
One can show [8] that events T [[A B]]
can be identified with a family of linear maps,
one for every C, that characterize the action of
T I
C
on [[AC]]
R
as a linear map to [[BC]]
R
.
As anticipated in the introductory paragraph, we
remind the reader that some of the difficulties
that we will be faced with in the remainder orig-
inate from the fact that in a general theory it is
not true that [[AB]]
R
= [[A]]
R
[[B]]
R
, but only
[[A]]
R
[[B]]
R
[[AB]]
R
. As a consequence, the lin-
ear map representing T on [[A]]
R
is not sufficient
to determine the linear map representing T I
C
on [[AC]]
R
.
One can easily prove that [[A B]] spans a real
vector space [[A B]]
R
. Being [[A B]] spanning
for [[A B]]
R
, the criteria of definition 1 and
lemma 1 hold for A , B [[A B]]
R
. Elements
of [[A B]]
R
are called generalized events. Every
space [[A B]]
R
has a zero event 0
AB
:
= 0
II
T [[A B]], where T is an arbitrary event in
[[A B]]. As a consequence of the coarse graining
rule for tests on [[I I]], one can easily show that
coarse graining of two or more transformations is
represented by their sum. Precisely, given a test
{T
i
}
iX
[[A B]], for X
0
= {0, 1} X one has
T
0
0
= T
0
+ T
1
, namely for every system C it is
T
0
0
I
C
= T
0
I
C
+ T
1
I
C
. Finally, every
set [[A B]] has a subset consisting in singleton
events, that we denote by [[A B]]
1
, and call
deterministic. For A, B 6= I, a deterministic event
is called channel. A channel U [[A B]]
1
is
reversible if there exists a channel V [[B A]]
1
such that V U = I
A
, U V = I
B
.
Let us now define the cones
[[A B]]
+
:
= {λT | λ 0, T [[A B]]}.
We will often write A 0 as a shorthand for
A [[A B]]
+
. The cone [[A B]]
+
introduces
a partial ordering in [[A B]]
R
, defined by
A B (A B) 0.
OPTs are assumed to have all sets [[A B]] (and
thus also cones [[A B]]
+
) closed in the opera-
tional norm.
Two systems may be operationally equivalent
if they can be mapped one onto the other via a
reversible transformation. Clearly, in this case
every processing of the first system is perfectly
simulated by a processing of the other, and vicev-
ersa.We define operationally equivalent systems
as follows.
Definition 2. Let A, B be two systems. We say
that A and B are operationally equivalent, in for-
mula A
=
B, if there exists a reversible transfor-
mation U [[A B]]
1
.
Definition 3. If A
1
and A
2
are operationally
equivalent through U and B
1
and B
2
through V ,
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 7
then, for every system C, A
1
[[A
1
C B
1
C]]
R
and A
2
[[A
2
C B
2
C]]
R
are operationally
equivalent if A
2
= (V I
C
)A
1
(U
1
I
C
). In
particular, ρ
1
[[A
1
C]]
R
and ρ
2
[[A
2
C]]
R
are
operationally equivalent if ρ
2
= (U I
C
)ρ
1
, and
a
1
[[
¯
A
1
¯
C]]
R
and a
2
[[
¯
A
2
¯
C]]
R
are operationally
equivalent if a
2
= a
1
(U
1
I
C
).
Lemma 2. Let AB be operationally equivalent to
A. Then B must be the trivial system I.
Proof. Since D
AB
D
A
D
B
D
A
, if AB
=
A
the chain of inequalities is saturated, and thus
D
B
= 1.
3.2 Causality and the no-restriction hypothesis
In the remainder of the paper we will focus on
causal theories. The causality property, that
we define right away, characterizes those theories
where signals can propagate only in the direc-
tion defined by input and output of processes,
within a cone of causal influence determined by
interactions between systems. These are the only
theories where one can consistently use informa-
tion acquired in a set of tests to condition the
choice of subsequent tests, where the partial or-
dering we are referring to is that determined by
the input/output direction.
Definition 4 (Causal theories). A theory (T , A)
is causal if for every test {T
i
}
iX
and every col-
lection of tests {S
i
j
}
jY
labelled by i Y, the
generalized test {C
i,j
}
(i,j)X×Y
with
A
C
i,j
C
:
=
A
T
i
B
S
i
j
C
,
is a test of the theory.
Notice that this notion of causality is strictly
stronger than the one usually adopted in the lit-
erature about OPTs, that can be summarised
as uniqueness of the deterministic effect (see
e.g. Refs. [8, 9, 15]). Indeed, a first result of
crucial importance derives uniqueness of the de-
terministic effect for every system type in causal
theories.
Theorem 1 ([8, 15]). In a causal theory, for ev-
ery system type A the set of deterministic effects
[[
¯
A]]
1
is the singleton {e
A
}.
A proof of the above theorem, that proceeds
by contradiction, can be found in the mentioned
references. We remark that, being the notion of
causality in these references different form the one
defined here, the theorem has a slightly different
statement. In the same references, one can find
the equivalence of uniqueness of the deterministic
effect with non-signalling from output to input.
Theorem 2 ([8, 15]). In an OPT, every system
type A has a unique deterministic effect if and
only if the marginal probabilities of preparation
tests cannot depend on the choice of subsequent
observation tests.
As a consequence of our notion of causality, in
a non-deterministic theory (i.e. a theory where
[[I]] 6= {0, 1}), every convex combination of tests
is a test (see e.g. [15]). This implies that the sets
[[A]]
, [[
¯
A]]
, [[A B]]
are convex, where can be
replaced by nothing, 1 or +. Moreover, the sets
with = + are convex cones.
Another important consequence of causality is
that a transformation C [[A B]] is determin-
istic if and only if it maps the deterministic effect
e
B
to the deterministic effect e
A
.
Theorem 3 ([8, 15]). In a causal theory, a trans-
formation C [[A B]] is a channel iff
A
C
B
e
=
A
e
.
In causal theories, one can always assume that
every state is proportional to a deterministic one.
Indeed, including in the theory every state ρ
[[A]]
+
such that (e
A
|ρ) = 1 does not introduce any
inconsistency with the set of transformations, as
we now prove. Let Θ be a causal OPT, and define
the theory Θ
0
through the bijection κ : Sys(Θ)
Sys
0
) :: A 7→ A
0
, with
[[A
0
B
0
]]
R
[[A B]]
R
,
[[A
0
B
0
]]
1
:
= {T 0 | (e
B
|T = (e
A
|},
[[A
0
B
0
]]
:
= {T 0 | C [[A
0
B
0
]]
1
, C T },
hhA
0
B
0
ii
:
= {T [[A
0
B
0
]] |
X
T T
T [[A
0
B
0
]]
1
}.
where denotes the ordering induced by the cones
of the theory Θ, and the cardinality of sets T
in the last definition is implicitly assumed to be
finite.
Theorem 4. Let Θ be a causal OPT, and con-
sider the theory Θ
0
defined above. Then Θ
0
is an
OPT with a unique deterministic effect e
A
0
for
every A
0
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 8
Proof. All the compositional structures of Θ are
inherited by Θ
0
. The defining conditions in the
special case of [[A
0
]] = [[I
0
A
0
]] give
[[A
0
]] = {ρ [[A]]
+
| (e
A
|ρ) 1},
while for [[
¯
A
0
]] = [[A
0
I
0
]] they give
[[
¯
A
0
]]
1
= {e
A
}.
What remains to be proved is that the set of
transformations is closed under sequential and
parallel composition. First of all, we observe that
by theorem 3 [[A B]]
1
[[A
0
B
0
]]
1
, thus
[[A B]] [[A
0
B
0
]]. This makes [[A B]]
+
[[A
0
B
0
]]
+
. On the other hand, since by def-
inition it is also [[A
0
B
0
]] [[A B]]
+
, we
have [[A
0
B
0
]]
+
[[A B]]
+
, which makes
[[A
0
B
0
]]
+
[[A B]]
+
. Thus the ordering is
the same for the two theories. As a consequence,
the preservation of cones under the two composi-
tions is inherited by Θ
0
from the same property in
Θ. Now, if A [[A
0
B
0
]]
1
and B [[B
0
C
0
]]
1
,
then
(e
C
|BA = (e
B
|A = (e
A
|,
thus BA [[A
0
C
0
]]
1
. Moreover, thanks to
causality of the theory Θ one has e
AB
= e
A
e
B
,
thus for A [[A
0
B
0
]]
1
and B [[C
0
D
0
]]
1
,
(e
BD
|A B = (e
B
|A (e
D
|B
= (e
A
| (e
C
| = (e
AC
|,
and consequently A B [[A
0
C
0
B
0
D
0
]]
1
.
Now, given events A , B in the theory Θ
0
, by defi-
nition we have C , D deterministic in Θ
0
such that
C A and D B, thus
F
:
=(D B)(C A ) + (D B)A
+ B(C A ) 0,
G
:
=(C A ) (D B)
+ (C A ) B + A (D B) 0.
Finally, F + BA BA and G + A B A
B are channels, and thus BA and A B are
events.
One can now show that the new theory Θ
0
is
causal.
Corollary 1. Let Θ be a causal OPT, and Θ
0
as
in theorem 4. Then Θ
0
is a causal OPT.
Proof. Let {T
i
}
iX
be a test in [[A
0
B
0
]], and
{S
i
j
}
jY
be tests in [[B
0
C
0
]] for every i X.
Then
i X
X
jY
(e
C
0
|S
i
j
= (e
B
0
|,
X
iX
(e
B
0
|T
i
= (e
A
0
|.
This implies that
X
iX
X
jY
(e
C
0
|W
i,j
= (e
A
0
|,
W
i,j
:
= S
i
j
T
i
[[A
0
C
0
]] i X, j Y.
As a consequence, every conditional test W
i,j
:
=
S
i
j
T
i
[[A
0
C
0
]] is admitted in the theory
Θ
0
.
Remark 1. In the remainder, we will focus on
theories satisfying causality and the further re-
quirements
[[A B]]
1
= {T 0 | (e
B
|T = (e
A
|},
[[A B]] = {T 0 | C [[A B]]
1
, C T },
hhA Bii = {T [[A B]] |
X
T T
T [[A B]]
1
}.
In particular, this implies that [[A]] = {ρ [[A]]
+
|
(e
A
|ρ) 1}. Thanks to corollary 1, this is not a
significant restriction.
We now narrow down focus on theories that
satisfy the no-restriction hypothesis. Let us con-
sider the set of preparation-tests for every system
of the theory Θ. Then we will complete the set
of tests allowing for all those tests that transform
preparation tests to preparation tests, even when
applied locally. This requirement is the general-
isation of the assumption made in quantum the-
ory that a map is a transformation if and only
if it is completely positive and trace non increas-
ing, and a collection of transformations is a test
if and only if the sum of its elements is a channel,
i.e. completely positive and trace-preserving.
Assumption 1. Let A [[A B]]
R
. The no-
restriction hypothesis consists in the requirement
that T hhA Bii if and only if for every C and
every P hhI ACii, one has (T I
C
)P hhI
BCii.
We will write A 0 if for every C and every
P [[AC]]
+
, one has (A I
C
)P [[BC]]
+
. The
set of transformations A 0 is a cone, that we
denote by
K(A B)
:
= {A [[A B]]
R
| A 0}.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 9
The above defined cone introduces a (partial) or-
dering in [[A B]]
R
, defined by
A B A B 0. (4)
Notice that, under the no-restriction hypothe-
sis, the following identity holds
K(A B) = [[A B]]
+
,
and thus for every A , B [[A B]]
R
,
A B A B. (5)
We remark that, under assumption 1, the hy-
pothesis of theorem 3 can be relaxed to C
[[A B]]
+
, since the latter implies that C = λC
0
for some C
0
[[A B]] and λ 0. Then,
C 0. Moreover, since C sends e
B
to e
A
,
one has (C I
C
)[[AC]]
1
[[BC]]
1
, and thus
(C I
C
)[[AC]] [[BC]]. By the no-restriction
hypothesis, this is tantamount to C [[A B]].
We can now prove a theorem that is a very
important consequence of the no-restriction hy-
pothesis, along with causality.
Theorem 5. In a theory satisfying the no-
restriction hypothesis, let T [[A B]]
R
. Then
T , C T 0 for some channel C [[A B]]
1
iff T [[A B]].
Proof. The hypothesis T , C T 0 is equiva-
lent to T , C T [[A B]]
+
. Equivalently,
for every C and every P [[AC]]
+
, one has
(X I
C
)P [[BC]]
+
for X = T , C T . Let
now P [[AC]]. Then one has
(e
BC
|[(C T ) I
C
]|P ) 0,
and thus
0 (e
BC
|(T I
C
)|P ) (e
AC
|P ) 1.
This implies that (T I
C
)P [[AC]]. Finally,
by the no-restriction hypothesis, T [[A B]].
The converse statement is trivial.
In the literature [10, 11] one can often find a dif-
ferent requirement under the name “no-restriction
hypothesis”, namely that for every system A the
set [[
¯
A]] coincides with the set of functionals a
on [[A]]
R
that satisfy 0 (a|ρ) 1 for ev-
ery ρ [[A]]. The last condition may be nei-
ther necessary nor sufficient for the no-restriction
hypothesis as we state it, despite counterexam-
ples are still unknown for both cases. Indeed,
the no-restriction hypothesis for effects imposes
the requirement that for every C and every state
P [[AC]], one has
P
A
a
C
[[C]] . (6)
3.3 Norms
As the first step in the present work is to con-
struct infinite composite systems, we will need a
thorough notion of sequences and limits. From a
topological point of view the vector spaces that
we constructed so far have no special structure,
however the operational procedures for discrim-
ination of processes provide a natural definition
of distance between events. Such a distance is re-
lated to the success probability in discriminating
events. Making the space of events into a metric
space, the operational distance immediately pro-
vides a topological structure through the induced
operational norm. However, in order to make the
space of events of infinite composite systems into
a Banach algebra, a stronger norm is needed, that
is introduced here: the sup-norm. In the quan-
tum and classical case the two norms coincide.
The operational norm k·k
op
for states is defined
as follows [15].
Definition 5. The operational norm on [[A]]
R
is
kρk
op
:
= sup
a[[
¯
A]]
(2a e|ρ) = sup
a
0
,a
1
[[
¯
A]]
a
0
+a
1
=e
A
(a
0
a
1
|ρ).
(7)
The operational norm k·k
op
for transformations
A [[A B]]
R
on finite systems is then defined
as
kA k
op
:
= sup
C,Ψ[[AC]]
1
k(A I
C
k
op
= sup
C,Ψ[[AC]]
sup
a[[
¯
B
¯
C]]
(2a e|
˜
A I
C
|Ψ).
In the special case of effects a [[
¯
A]]
R
we have
kak
op
:
= sup
C,Ψ[[AC]]
k(a I
C
k
op
= sup
C,Ψ[[AC]]
sup
b[[
¯
C]]
(a [2b e
C
]|Ψ).
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 10
As a consequence,
kak
op
= sup
ρ
0
1
[[A]]
ρ
0
+ρ
1
[[A]]
(a|ρ
0
ρ
1
)
= sup
p[0,1]
{p sup
ρ[[A]]
(a|ρ) (1 p) inf
σ[[A]]
(a|σ)}
= max{ sup
ρ[[A]]
(a|ρ), inf
σ[[A]]
(a|σ)}
= sup
ρ[[A]]
|(a|ρ)|.
Here we only prove one new result about the op-
erational norm, that we will use in the following.
Lemma 3. Let ρ [[A]]
R
and σ [[B]]
1
. Then
kρ σk
op
= kρk
op
. (8)
Proof. By definition it is
kρ σk
op
= sup
(a
0
,a
1
)
(a
0
a
1
|ρ σ)
= sup
(b
0
,b
1
)M
(b
0
b
1
|ρ),
where M
:
= {(b
0
, b
1
) | b
i
= a
i
(I
A
σ)}. Thus
kρ σk
op
kρk
op
.
On the other hand, for every binary observation-
test (a
0
, a
1
) in [[
¯
A]] one has
a
i
= (a
i
e
B
)(I
A
σ),
and thus M actually contains every possible bi-
nary observation-test on A. Finally, this implies
that
kρ σk
op
= kρk
op
.
For more details on k·k
op
see Refs. [8, 15].
We now proceed to define the sup-norm.
Definition 6. The sup-norm kA k
sup
of A
[[A B]]
R
is defined as
kA k
sup
:
= inf J(A ),
J(B)
:
= {λ | C [[A B]]
1
, λC B λC }.
We now show that k·k
sup
actually defines a
norm.
Proposition 1. The sup-norm on [[A B]]
R
is
well defined:
1. kA k
sup
is non-negative, and it is null iff
A = 0,
2. for µ R one has kµA k
sup
= |µ|kA k
sup
,
3. kA + Bk
sup
kA k
sup
+ kBk
sup
.
Proof. 1. Let A [[A B]]
R
. Suppose that
j
:
= inf J(A ) < 0. Then there exists 0 < ε < |j|
such that j + ε J(A ), namely
(|j| ε)C A (|j| ε)C
2(|j| ε)C 0,
for some C [[A B]]
1
, which is absurd. Then
inf J(A ) 0. Suppose now that J(A ) = 0.
This implies that for every n N there exists
C
n
[[A B]]
1
such that
1
n
C
n
A
1
n
C
n
.
Now, by the closure of [[A]]
+
in the operational
norm, and considering that the sequences (
1
n
C
n
±
A ) converge to ±A , it must be ±A [[A]]
+
.
This is possible if and only if A = 0. 2. The
proof is trivial for µ = 0. Let then µ 6= 0. If
x J(A ), then xC ± A 0 for some C
[[A B]]
1
, and thus |µ|(xC ± A ) 0, namely
|µ|x J(µA ). Thus kµA k
sup
|µ|kA k
sup
. For
the same reason, kA k
sup
(1/|µ|)kµA k
sup
, and
finally kµA k
sup
= |µ|kA k
sup
. 3. Let now x
J(A ) and y J(B). Then xC ± A 0, and
yD ± B 0, for C , D [[A B]]
1
. Thus (x +
y)F ± (A + B) 0, where F
:
= x/(x + y)C +
y/(x+y)D [[A B]]
1
. Thus, x+y J(A +B),
and then kA + Bk
sup
kA k
sup
+ kBk
sup
.
The following property makes ([[A
A]]
R
, k·k
sup
) a Banach algebra.
Proposition 2. For A [[B C]]
R
and B
[[A B]]
R
, kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
.
Proof. Let x J(A ), and y J(B). Then there
are C , D such that xC ± A 0, yD ± B 0.
Now, we have
1
2
[(xC + A )(yD B) + (xC A )(yD + B)
= xyC D A B 0
1
2
[(xC + A )(yD + B) + (xC A )(yD B)
=xyC D + A B 0,
and then xy J(A B). Thus, kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
.
Lemma 4. Let A [[A B]]
R
, and for an arbi-
trary C, let D [[C D]]
1
. Then kA Dk
sup
=
kA k
sup
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 11
Proof. Let x J(A ). Then by definition there
exists C [[A B]]
1
such that xC ± A 0.
This implies that
xC D ± A D 0,
namely x J(A D), and then J(A ) J(A
D). Now, let y J(A D). Then there exists
C
0
[[AC BD]]
1
such that yC
0
± A D 0.
Composing the l.h.s. of the latter relation with
ψ [[C]]
1
and e
D
, we obtain yC
00
± A 0,
where C
00
:
= (e
D
|C
0
|ψ) is a channel, and then
y J(A ). Thus, J(A D) J(A ). Finally,
since J(A D) = J(A ), we have kA Dk
sup
=
kA k
sup
.
Corollary 2. For A [[A B]]
R
, and for arbi-
trary C, it is kA I
C
k
sup
= kA k
sup
.
Corollary 3. For A [[A B]]
R
and B
[[C D]]
R
, kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
.
Proof. The result follows straightforwardly from
proposition 2 and corollary 2.
An important result regarding the sup-norm is
provided by the following proposition.
Proposition 3. For A [[B C]]
R
and B
[[A B]]
R
, kA Bk
op
kA k
sup
kBk
op
.
Proof. By definition we have
kA Bk
op
= sup
D,Ψ[[AD]]
1
sup
a[[
¯
C
¯
D]]
(2a e
CD
|A B I
D
|Ψ).
Now, for every a [[
¯
C
¯
D]], and λ J(A ), upon
defining a
0
:
= a, a
1
:
= e
CD
a, we have
(a
0
a
1
|A I
C
= (a
0
|[A I
D
] (a
1
|[A I
D
]
= λ[(˜a
0
| (˜a
1
|],
where a
i
|
:
= λ
1
{(a
i
|[A I
D
]+
1
2
(e|[(λC A )
I
D
]}, with C : [[B C]]
1
such that λC ± A 0.
Clearly,
˜a
0
, ˜a
1
[[
¯
B
¯
D]], ˜a
0
+ ˜a
1
= e
BD
,
thus
(a
0
a
1
|A B I
D
|Ψ)
= λ[(˜a
0
| (˜a
1
|]B I
D
|Ψ)
λ sup
b[[
¯
B
¯
D]]
(2b e
BD
|B I
D
|Ψ)
This implies that kA Bk
op
λ sup
b[[
¯
B
¯
D]]
(2b
e
BD
|B I
D
|Ψ), and then for every λ J(A )
kA Bk
op
λ sup
D,Ψ[[AD]]
1
sup
b[[
¯
B
¯
D]]
(2b e
BD
|B I
D
|Ψ)
= λkBk
op
.
Finally, taking the infimum over λ J(A ) we
get
kA Bk
op
kA k
sup
kBk
op
.
Corollary 4. The sup-norm is stronger than the
operational norm.
Proof. It is sufficient to observe that kA k
op
=
kA I k
op
kA k
sup
kI k
op
= kA k
sup
.
Lemma 5. Let A [[A B]]
1
be a channel.
Then kA k
sup
= 1.
Proof. Clearly, A A A , thus 1 J(A ),
and inf J(A ) 1. On the other hand, suppose
that there exists 1 > λ J(A ). This implies
that there exists a channel C [[A B]]
1
such
that D
:
= λC A 0. However, this implies
that (e|
B
D = (1 λ)(e|
A
0. This is ab-
surd, and then λ J(A ) must be λ 1. Thus,
inf J(A ) 1. Finally, this implies kA k
sup
=
1.
Corollary 5. The sup-norm of the identity chan-
nel I [[A A]]
1
is 1.
The sup-norm for effects is just the special case
of the sup-norm of transformations with the out-
put system equal to I.
Definition 7. Let a [[
¯
A]]
R
, and let us define
the half-line
J(a)
:
= {λ R
+
| λe
A
a λe
A
}.
The sup-norm kak
sup
is defined as
kak
sup
:
= inf J(a).
Proposition 4. The sup-norm on [[
¯
A]]
R
is well
defined:
1. kak
sup
is non-negative, and it is null iff a =
0,
2. for µ R one has kµak
sup
= |µ|kak
sup
,
3. ka + bk
sup
kak
sup
+ kbk
sup
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 12
Proof. The case of effects is just a special case of
the result of Proposition 1.
As an immediate consequence of proposition 3,
we have the following result.
Corollary 6. The sup-norm is stronger than the
operational norm on [[
¯
A]]
R
.
In the special case of [[I I]]
R
= R, one has
[[I I]]
1
= {1}, and [[I I]]
+
= R
+
, thus J(x) =
{λ R | λ±x 0}. Clearly, kxk
sup
= inf J(x) =
|x|. We now need the following lemma.
Lemma 6. Let a [[
¯
A]]
R
. Then ka e
B
k
op
=
kak
op
and ka e
B
k
sup
= kak
sup
.
Proof. For k·k
op
, the equality trivially follows
from the definition. For k·k
sup
, it is a special
case of lemma 4.
From lemma 5, the following consequence fol-
lows.
Corollary 7. For the deterministic effect e
A
one
has ke
A
k
sup
= ke
A
k
op
= 1.
We now prove a result that will be very useful
later.
Lemma 7. Let A [[A B]]
+
, and (a|
:
=
(e
B
|A [[
¯
A]]
+
. Then kA k
sup
= kak
sup
.
Proof. First of all, by proposition 2, one has
kak
sup
ke
A
k
sup
kA k
sup
= kA k
sup
. On the
other hand, let λ J(a). This implies that
b
:
= λe
A
a 0.
Let us then define B
:
= |ρ)(b| [[A B]]
+
, for
some ρ [[B]]
1
. By theorem 3, it is easy to check
that A + B = λC for C [[A B]]
1
. Then,
λC A = B 0, (9)
which means that λ J(A ). Then, J(a)
J(A ), and finally kA k
sup
kak
sup
.
In the case of Classical and Quantum Theory,
phrasing the definitions of sup- and operational
norm in terms of semidefinite programming prob-
lems, one can conclude that they are strongly
dual. As a consequence, in these special cases
they define the same norm.
4 The quasi-local algebra in OPTs
Following the definition of Ref. [31], we de-
fine a cellular automaton in a general OPT as
a triple (G, A, V ), where G is a denumerable
set of labels for the systems that compose the
automaton—addresses of the memory cells—, A
G
is a (possibly infinite) composite system corre-
sponding to the collection of systems A
g
labelled
by elements g G—i.e. the memory array—, and
V is a reversible transformation on [[
¯
A
G
]], such
that V · V
1
is an automorphism of [[A
G
A
G
]].
However, this is definition is incomplete, for many
reasons. In the first place, most of the objects
mentioned above are not thoroughly defined. The
purpose of the present section is to set the ground
for the rigorous definition of a cellular automaton.
We start fixing some notation. For every R
G let
A
R
:
=
O
gR
A
g
,
with the convention that A
:
= I. The full sys-
tem is then A
G
=
N
gG
A
g
. This purely formal
notion will now be thoroughly substantiated.
With a slight abuse of notation, we will often
use R = g instead of R = {g}, dropping the
braces. The set of finite regions of G will be de-
noted as
R
(G)
:
= {R G | |R| < ∞},
while the set of arbitrary regions of G will be
denoted as
R
(G)
:
= {R G}.
Clearly R
(G)
R
(G)
. In the remainder, when we
write e.g. e
R
or I
R
for R R
(G)
, we mean the
deterministic effect or the identity transformation
for the system A
R
, respectively.
The following construction of
N
gG
A
g
is in-
spired by that of Refs. [49, 50], however with sig-
nificant differences.
4.1 Quasi-local effects
In this subsection we start the mathematical con-
struction of the system A
G
, the parallel compo-
sition of infinitely many finite systems. The first
object that we will define is the space of gener-
alised effects, along with its convex cone of pos-
itive effects, and the convex set of effects. The
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 13
construction is based on the notion of a local ef-
fect, that is an effect which acts non trivially only
on finitely many systems labelled by g R, with
R R
(G)
. We will say that such an effect acts
on the finite region R. We will then introduce a
real vector space structure over the set of local
effects, and a norm that is induced by the sup
norm for local effects. The last step is then the
topological closure of the space of local effects in
the sup-norm. The Banach space thus obtained
is the space of generalised quasi-local effects, and
the positive cone along with the convex set of ef-
fects contain the limits of sequences of elements of
local cones or convex sets of effects, respectively.
As we will see in the next section, the definition
of the space of quasi-local states is much more in-
volved than that of quasi-local effects. The latter
is particularly simple, thanks to causality, that
provides us with a preferential local effect, the
unique deterministic one, without the need of in-
troducing any arbitrary choice of a reference local
effect. Moreover, while the construction of the
space of quasi-local states is not logically nec-
essary, as we will find them as a subspace of
bounded functionals on quasi-local effects, the
same is not true of effects.
If we defined effects as the dual space of quasi-
local states, we would end up with far more effects
than needed, while lacking sectors of the state
space, that are usually reached by the evolution of
a quasi-local state through a cellular automaton.
These are the main reasons why our construction
begins with effects.
The first notion we introduce is that of a lo-
cal effect. Let A
G
denote the formal composition
of countably many systems from a general OPT:
A
G
:
=
N
gG
A
g
. Intuitively speaking, a local ef-
fect of A
G
is an event within a test that discards
all the systems in G but the finite region R, where
a non-trivial measurement is performed. We then
define the local effect (a, R) as a pair made of an
effect a [[
¯
A
R
]] and the region R. To lighten the
notation, in the remainder of the paper we will
use the symbol a
R
instead of (a, R). The set of
local effects is denoted by
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
L
:
=
G
RR
(G)
[[
¯
A
R
]] = {a
R
| R R
(G)
, a [[
¯
A
R
]]}.
The above definition can be widened encompass-
ing generalised effects:
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
:
=
G
RR
(G)
[[
¯
A
R
]]
R
.
Let us now consider a partition of the region R
into two disjoint regions S
0
S
1
= R. Since in
the definition of a local effect a
R
we did not set
constraints on the effect a [[
¯
A
R
]]
R
, it might be
that a = e
S
0
a
0
, with a
0
[[
¯
A
S
1
]]
R
. It is clear
from our intuitive notion of a local effect that a
R
and a
0
S
1
should represent the same effect. This
observation leads us to the equivalence relation
defined as follows.
Definition 8 (Equivalent local effects). We say
that the effects a
R
and a
0
S
in Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
are
equivalent, and denote this as a
R
a
0
S
, if there
exists a
0
[[
¯
A
RS
]]
R
such that the following iden-
tities hold
(
a = a
0
e
S\R
,
a
0
= a
0
e
R\S
.
(10)
It is clear that the real notion of a local ef-
fect is captured by the equivalence classes modulo
the above equivalence relation. We thus quotient
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
R
and define the obtained set as the set
of local effects of A
G
.
Definition 9. A generalised local effect is an
equivalence class [a
R
]
. The set of generalised
local effects of A
G
is
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
:
= Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
/ .
With a slight abuse of notation, in the following
we will write a
R
instead of [a
R
]
, unless the con-
text requires explicit distinction of the two sym-
bols. One can easily prove the following result
Lemma 8. Let a
R
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
. Then for every
finite region H R
(G)
such that H R = ,
one has (a e
H
)
RH
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, and (a
e
H
)
RH
a
R
.
The proof of the above lemma is straightfor-
ward, and we do not report it here.
Let us now come back to our initial goal, that
is to define a local effect as an event that acts
non-trivially only on a finite region R. Intuition
leads again to figure out what is the preferred
representative of the class of a local effect: within
the equivalence class, it is the element defined on
the smallest region. We now provide a formal
definition of such a minimal representative, and
show that it is well posed.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 14
Definition 10. The minimal representative of
the equivalence class a
R
, denoted as ˜a
R
a
, is de-
fined through
R
a
:
=
\
SR
(a,R)
S, ˜a
R
a
a
R
, (11)
where R
(a,R)
is the set of all those finite regions
S R
(G)
for which there exists b [[
¯
A
S
]]
R
such
that b
S
a
R
.
Lemma 9. The minimal representative exists
and is unique.
Proof. As to existence, we remark that, by
Eq. (11), R
a
is the set of all g G such that
for all regions S R
(a,R)
one has g S. Thus,
if h 6∈ R
a
, there must exist S R
(a,R)
such that
h 6∈ S. This implies that i) by definition there
exists f
S
a
R
, and ii) by lemma 8 c
Sh
a
R
,
with
c = f e
h
. (12)
As a consequence, if c
T
a
R
and h T , but
h 6∈ R
a
, by definition (10) c
T
must be of the
form of Eq. (12), for some f [[
¯
A
T \h
]]
R
. Clearly,
R
a
R
(G)
, since for any S R
(a,R)
one has R
a
S. Now, let S R
(a,R)
, and c
S
a
R
. One has
S = R
a
S
0
, where S
0
:
= (S \ R
a
) R
(G)
, thus
R
a
S
0
= . By Eq. (12), we then have
c = b e
S
0
, b [[
¯
A
R
a
]]
R
. (13)
We now define ˜a
R
a
:
= b
R
a
, and finally, since
Eq. 13 holds for any c
S
a
R
, one can easily
verify that ˜a
R
a
a
R
.
As to uniqueness, we remark that the re-
gion R
a
is uniquely defined. Now, suppose that
there were two different b, c [[
¯
A
R
a
]]
R
such that
b
R
a
, c
R
a
a
R
. Then by Eq. (10) it must be
b = c.
We now make local effects into a vector space.
Definition 11. Let a
R
, b
S
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, and h R.
Then we define
ha
R
:
=
(
(ha)
R
h 6= 0,
0
h = 0,
a
R
+ b
S
:
= c
RS
c
:
= a e
S\R
+ b e
R\S
.
Notice that it is not always true that R
c
= R
a
R
b
. As an example, consider a = f
g
1
f
g
2
and b =
f
g
1
(e f
g
2
), with f
g
1
6= e
g
1
, 0 6= f
g
2
6= e
g
2
, and
R
a
= R
b
= {g
1
, g
2
}. Then c = a + b = f
g
1
e
g
2
,
and clearly R
c
= {g
1
}, which is strictly included
in R
a
= R
b
= R
a
R
b
.
It is easy to check that [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
is a real vector
space with null element given by the equivalence
class of 0
.
We now equip the real vector space of local
effects with a norm, and we then close it to ob-
tain the Banach space of quasi-local effects. The
definition is based on a norm for effects of finite
systems, as every local effect a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
re-
duces to the effect ˜a [[
¯
A
R
a
]]
R
. A natural norm
one might think of is then the operational norm,
that induces the following definition.
Definition 12. The operational norm ka
R
k
op
of
a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
is defined by the following expres-
sion
ka
R
k
op
:
= k˜ak
op
, (14)
where ˜a [[
¯
A
R
a
]]
R
.
Unfortunately, if one completes the space of
local effects in the operational norm, in general
the dual norm on the space of bounded linear
functionals—which will be our state space—does
not coincide with the operational norm on the
state space, for those states that can be inter-
preted as quasi-local preparations. We will then
choose a different norm on our space of effects.
The new norm will be referred to as sup-norm, as
it is the extension of the sup-norm to the infinite
case.
As far as finite-dimensional systems are con-
cerned, this choice does not represent a problem,
as all norms are equivalent in finite-dimensional
vector spaces. However, the sup-norm is stronger
than the operational one—see corollary 4—, and
thus the space that we construct, completing our
normed vector space of local effects with sup-
norm Cauchy sequences, might contain distinct
limits that are operationally equivalent. This
point is a delicate one, and to avoid an unreason-
able construction where there exist different ef-
fects that are operationally equivalent, we impose
a sufficient constraint for the operational norm
and the sup-norm to be equivalent also for infi-
nite systems: we restrict attention to those the-
ories where the following property holds: there
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 15
exists a finite constant k such that for every sys-
tem A and every a [[
¯
A]]
R
kak
sup
kkak
op
. (15)
This implies that not only the bound (15) holds
for a fixed system A, but it holds with a fixed
constant independent of the system A. In turn,
a sufficient condition for (15) is that for every
system A
[[A]]
+
[[
¯
A]]
+
, (16)
namely every positive functional on the cone of
states is proportional to an effect by a positive
constant, and viceversa. In all the presently
known theories the latter condition is satisfied.
The two above conditions in Eqs. (15) and (16)
are discussed in detail in Appendix A, where we
prove that condition (16) implies condition (15).
Our new norm is an order-unit norm. As we
will discuss in subsection 4.2, its dual coincides
with the operational norm on quasi-local states.
Let us now see the definition of the sup-norm
in detail.
Definition 13. The sup-norm ka
R
k
sup
of a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
is defined by the following expression
ka
R
k
sup
:
= k˜ak
sup
, (17)
where ˜a [[
¯
A
R
a
]]
R
.
We now want to prove that the operational
norm and the sup-norm are well-defined norms
on [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
.
Proposition 5. Let a
R
˜a
R
a
. Then ka
R
k
op
=
kak
op
, and ka
R
k
sup
= kak
sup
.
Proof. Let a
R
˜a
R
a
, and R = R
a
R
0
, with
R
a
R
0
= . Then by Eq. (10) we have
a = ˜a e
R
0
,
and thus by definitions 12 and 13 and lemma 6,
it is
ka
R
k
op
= k˜ak
op
= k˜a e
R
0
k
op
= kak
op
,
ka
R
k
sup
= k˜ak
sup
= k˜a e
R
0
k
sup
= kak
sup
.
We can then prove the desired result.
Proposition 6. The functionals k·k
op
and k·k
sup
are norms on [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
.
Proof. 1. For every a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
it is clear that
ka
R
k
op
0 and ka
R
k
sup
0. Now, k˜ak
op
=
k˜ak
sup
= 0 if and only if ˜a = 0, namely, re-
minding definition 11, a
R
= 0
. 2. For every
a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, by definitions 7, 11, and 12, one
straightforwardly has that, for every µ R,
kµa
R
k
op
= kµ˜ak
op
= |µ|k˜ak
op
= |µ|ka
R
k
op
,
kµa
R
k
sup
= kµ˜ak
sup
= |µ|k˜ak
sup
= |µ|ka
R
k
sup
.
3. Let now c
RS
= a e
S\R
+ e
R\S
b for
a [[
¯
A
R
]]
R
and b [[
¯
A
S
]]
R
, as from definition 11.
Then, by lemma 6, proposition 5 and by the tri-
angle inequality, we have
ka
R
+ b
S
k
op
= kc
RS
k
op
= kck
op
kak
op
+ kbk
op
= ka
R
k
op
+ kb
S
k
op
,
ka
R
+ b
S
k
sup
= kc
RS
k
sup
= kck
sup
kak
sup
+ kbk
sup
= ka
R
k
sup
+ kb
S
k
sup
.
We remark that, in a theory that satisfies as-
sumption (16), one has k·k
op
k·k
sup
on [[
¯
A]]
R
,
and thus k·k
op
= k·k
sup
on [[
¯
A
G
]]
R
(the proof can
be found in appendix A). In general, however, the
sup-norm is stronger than the operational norm,
as we now prove.
Lemma 10. Let a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
. Then ka
R
k
op
ka
R
k
sup
.
Proof. Let us consider µ J(a). Then for every
ρ [[A
R
]]
1
we have
(µe
R
± a|ρ) 0,
i.e. |(a|ρ)| µ. Then, taking the supremum over
states on l.h.s. we obtain ka
R
k
op
µ, and finally,
taking the infimum over J(a) we obtain the the-
sis.
The space of local effects that we constructed
so far is a normed real vector space. We now
make it into a Banach space, the space of quasi-
local effects, by the usual completion procedure
for normed spaces. We first introduce the space
[[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
of Cauchy sequences
a : N [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
:: n 7→ a
n
R
n
.
We then define the equivalence relation between
Cauchy sequences in [[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
defined by a
=
b
iff lim
n→∞
ka
n
R
n
b
n
S
n
k
sup
= 0. Finally, we de-
fine the space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
of generalised quasi-local
effects, by taking the quotient
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
:
= [[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
/
=
. (18)
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 16
The elements of this space will be denoted by
a = [a
n
R
n
]. In this context, the class of a con-
stant Cauchy sequence (R
n
= R and a
n
R
n
= a
R
)
will be denoted by a
R
:
= [a
n
R
n
]. Clearly, since
|ka
n
R
n
k
sup
ka
m
R
m
k
sup
| ka
n
R
n
a
m
R
m
k
sup
,
for a Cauchy sequence a = [a
n
R
n
] also ka
n
R
n
k
sup
is a Cauchy sequence, and we define kak
sup
:
=
lim
n→∞
ka
n
R
n
k
sup
. One can easily verify that
the sup-norm on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
thus defined is indepen-
dent of the specific sequence within an equiva-
lence class. The space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
is by construction
a real Banach space, and [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
can be identi-
fied with the dense submanifold containing con-
stant sequences a
R
= [a
R
]. Clearly, in this case
kak
sup
= ka
R
k
sup
.
Definition 14. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. If there is a
Cauchy sequence a
n
R
n
in the class defining a,
such that, for some n
0
N, for every n n
0
one has ˜a
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
]], then we call a a quasi-local
effect. We denote the set of quasi-local effects by
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
The cone [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
contains all elements that
are proportional to an element in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
by a pos-
itive constant.
The deterministic quasi-local effect e
G
is the
class e
G
:
= 1
.
The cone [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
introduces a partial ordering
in [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, that we denote by
a b a b [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Quasi-local effects can be interpreted as effects
that can be arbitrarily well approximated by local
observation procedures. The effect e
G
plays an
important role, as it is the unique deterministic
effect in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. This will be proved shortly. Let
us start providing the first important property of
e
G
.
Lemma 11. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. Then also e
G
a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. Let a = [a
n
R
n
]. Let a
0
n
R
n
:
= (e a
n
)
R
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
]]. Then one has (a
0
n
a
0
m
)
R
n
R
m
= (a
m
a
n
)
R
m
R
n
, and thus a
0
n
R
n
is a Cauchy sequence
whose class we call a
0
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. Finally, since
a+a
0
is the class [a
n
R
n
]+[a
0
n
R
n
] = [(a
n
+a
0
n
)
R
n
] =
[1
] = e
G
, we have that a + a
0
= e
G
, namely
e
G
a = a
0
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
By the above lemma we know that not only
e
G
a for every quasi-local effect a, but also that
every quasi-local effect a can be complemented
by a quasi-local effect a
0
such that a + a
0
= e
G
.
In other words (a, e
G
a) is a binary quasi-local
observation test.
We can also prove the converse result.
Lemma 12. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
, and e
G
a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
. Then a, e
G
a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. Indeed, the statement is true for finite
systems thanks to the no-restriction hypothesis
(see theorem 5), and thus it holds for a given
Cauchy sequence in the class of a, namely if
a
0
n
R
n
:
= (e a
n
)
R
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
]]
+
for all n, then
a
n
, a
0
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
]]. Thus, a = lim
n→∞
a
n
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
,
and a
0
= lim
n→∞
a
0
n
= e
G
a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
We now prove that e
G
lies in the interior of
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
, namely there is a ball of radius r around
e
G
in sup-norm that is contained in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Lemma 13. There exists an open ball B
r
(e
G
)
of radius r in [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
that is fully contained in
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Proof. Let ka e
G
k
sup
< r < 1/2. Then, by
definition, there exist a sequence a
n
R
n
such that
lim
n→∞
a
n
= a, and n
0
N such that for n n
0
ka
n
e
G
k
sup
ka
n
ak
sup
+ ka e
G
k
sup
< 2r.
This implies that
[2re + (a
n
e)]
R
n
= [a
n
(1 2r)e]
R
n
0.
Now, this implies that for n n
0
it is a
n
(1 2r)e
R
n
0, and thus a
n
[[
¯
A
G
]]
L+
. Finally,
by definition, one obtains a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
. Thus, the
ball B
r
(e
G
) is contained in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Corollary 8. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
. Then for ε > 0,
B
εr
(εe
G
+ a) [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
for some r > 0.
Proof. Let b B
εr
(εe
G
+ a). Then
kb a εe
G
k
sup
< εr
k(b a) e
G
k
sup
< r.
Then (b a) = c [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
, ad thus
b = εc + a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
We now prove that the deterministic effect e
G
allows for an extension of the defining property
of the sup-norm.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 17
Lemma 14. The sup-norm of a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
can
be expressed as
kak
sup
= inf J(a),
J(a)
:
= {µ 0 | µe
G
a µe
G
}.
Proof. In the case of local effects a = a
R
the
statement is a trivial recasting of the definition
of sup-norm. Let us then consider the class a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
with a = [a
n
R
n
]. One has, by definition,
kak
sup
= lim
n→∞
ka
n
k
sup
. Let us consider the
sequence µ
n
:
= ka
n
k
sup
+ ε J(a
n
). Clearly,
lim
n→∞
µ
n
= kak
sup
+ ε. Moreover, since
k{(µ
n
µ
m
)e ± (a
n
a
m
)}
R
n
R
m
k
sup
|ka
m
k
sup
ka
n
k
sup
| + ka
m
a
n
k
sup
2ε,
the sequence {(µ
n
+ ε)e ± a
n
}
R
n
converges to
(kak
sup
+ε)e
G
±a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
, thus for every ε 0
one has kak
sup
+ ε J(a). This implies that
inf J(a) kak
sup
.
On the other hand, let µ J(a), then
µe
G
± a 0.
By corollary 8, we have that, for ε > 0,
(ε + µ)e
G
± a B
εr
(εe
G
+ µe
G
± a) [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Now, this implies that there are two open balls,
centred at (µ + ε)e
G
± a, that are fully contained
in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
. There exists then n
0
N such that
for n n
0
one has
(µ + ε)e
G
± a
n
0,
namely (µ + ε) J(a
n
). Thus, J(a) J(a
n
) ε,
and
inf J(a) ka
n
k
sup
ε. (19)
Finally, this implies that inf J(a) kak
sup
.
As the cone [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
is closed, we can easily
prove that the infimum in the expression of the
sup norm is actually a minimum.
Lemma 15. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. Then
kak
sup
e
G
± a 0. (20)
Proof. By lemma 14, for every ε > 0 one has
(kak
sup
+ ε)e
G
± a 0.
The sequences b
±
n
:
= (kak
sup
+1/n)e
G
±a are both
Cauchy, and their limits are both in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
,
then
kak
sup
e
G
± a 0.
Before concluding, we remark that the opera-
tional norm can be extended to [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, by sim-
ply defining for a = [a
n
R
n
]
kak
op
:
= lim
n→∞
ka
n
R
n
k
op
.
Indeed, since
|ka
n
R
n
k
op
ka
m
R
m
k
op
| ka
n
R
n
a
m
R
m
k
op
ka
n
R
n
a
m
R
m
k
sup
,
the sequence ka
n
R
n
k
op
is Cauchy, and the limit
is well defined. Moreover, also on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
the sup-norm is stronger than the operational
norm, as can be straightforwardly concluded from
lemma 10. However, in theories where there ex-
ists k > 0 such that k·k
sup
kk·k
op
in [[
¯
A]]
R
for
every finite system A, the same inequality holds
in the limit, and the operational and sup-norm
are equivalent. In particular, this is the case un-
der assumption (16).
We now introduce a diagrammatic notation for
effects in [[
¯
A]]
QR
that will make part of the subse-
quent proofs and arguments more intuitive. First
of all, we denote a quasi-local effect a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
by the symbol
G
a
. (21)
In the case of a local effect a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, we will
draw
G
a
R
=
R
a
G\R
e
. (22)
Notice that, since for (a e
R
1
)
R
with a [[
¯
A
R
0
]]
and R
1
:
= R \ R
0
, it is (a e
R
1
)
R
a
R
0
, we have
R
0
a
R
1
e
G\R
e
=
R
0
a
(G\R)R
1
e
. (23)
From the above identity, we can intuitively con-
clude that
(G\R)R
1
e
=
R
1
e
G\R
e
. (24)
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 18
Indeed, let G = R H, with |R| < . Then
[e
R
] = [1
] = e
G
, which is the equation repre-
sented by the diagram in Eq. 24. Similarly, let
a
R
b
H
:
= lim
n→∞
(a b
n
), where [b
nS
n
] = b
[[
¯
A
H
]]
QR
. By corollary 3, one has [(ab
n
)
RS
n
] =
(a
R
b
H
). Thus, in G = R H, one has
a
R
= [a
R
] = [(a
R
e
H
)] = a
R
e
H
, which is
the meaning of Eq. (22).
As a final remark, we observe that for every
denumerable set G, and every subset R G, in-
cluding infinite ones, one can define [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
as
the closed subspace spanned by those quasi-local
effects a = a
n
R
n
such that, for every n N, R
n
R. If one constructs the system A
R
:
=
N
gR
A
g
,
it is straightforward to construct an ordered Ba-
nach space isomorphism
J
R
: [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
R
]]
QR
:: [a
n
R
n
]
G
7→ [a
n
R
n
]
R
,
(25)
with the norm coinciding with the sup-norm in
both spaces. The left-inverse of J
R
is
J
1
R
: [[
¯
A
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
. (26)
J
R
and J
1
R
can be diagrammatically denoted
as
R
J
R
R
a
G\R
e
=
R
a
,
(27)
G
J
1
R
R
a
=
R
a
G\R
e
. (28)
4.2 Extended states
Now that we defined the space of quasi-local ef-
fects, we can define the space of states as the
space of bounded linear functionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
.
The set of states is then defined considering those
linear functionals that, acting on local effects of
an arbitrary finite region R, behave as a state in
[[A
R
]].
Definition 15 (Generalised extended states).
The space [[A
G
]]
R
of generalised extended states
of A
G
is the topological dual of [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, i.e. the
Banach space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
of bounded linear function-
als on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, equipped with the norm
kρk
:
= sup
kak
sup
=1
|(a|ρ)|. (29)
The operational norm on [[A
G
]]
R
, defined as
kρk
op
:
= sup
a[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
(2a e
G
|ρ), (30)
coincides with the norm k·k
, as we now prove.
Lemma 16. Let ρ [[A
G
]]
R
. Then
kρk
= sup
a[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
(2a e
G
|ρ). (31)
Proof. Let 0 ε kρk
op
. We then have
0 kρk
op
ε (2a e
G
|ρ),
for some a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. Invoking lemma 11, one has
e
G
+ (2a e
G
) = 2a 0,
e
G
(2a e
G
) = 2(e
G
a) 0,
and, by lemma 14, k2a e
G
k
sup
1. Then it is
kρk
op
ε
(2a e
G
|ρ)
k2a e
G
k
sup
kρk
.
On the other hand, let us now pick a [[
¯
A
G
]]
R
with kak
sup
= 1. Then, by lemma 15, e
G
±a 0.
If we define a
±
:
=
1
2
(e
G
± a), we have a
±
0,
and
a
+
+ a
= e
G
, (a
+
a
) = a, (32)
which by lemma 12 implies that a
±
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Then
±(a|ρ) = (2a
±
e
G
|ρ).
Thus, |(a|ρ)| kρk
op
, for every ε > 0, and taking
the supremum on the l.h.s. we obtain kρk
kρk
op
.
Technically speaking, the two norms k·k
sup
and
k·k
are a base and order-unit norm pair [51].
What is missing now is the notion of a convex
set of proper states, the extended preparations of
our infinite system A
G
. Let us then give the fol-
lowing definition.
Definition 16 (Local restriction). Given a state
ρ [[A
G
]]
R
, the local restriction of ρ to S R
(G)
is the functional ρ
|S
[[A
S
]]
R
defined through
(a|ρ
|S
)
:
= (a
S
|ρ), a [[
¯
A
S
]]. (33)
The notion of a restriction can be brought fur-
ther, considering infinite regions, by invoking the
isomorphism J
R
defined in Eq. (25), as follows.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 19
Definition 17 (Restriction). Given a state ρ
[[A
G
]]
R
, the restriction of ρ to S R
(G)
is the
functional ρ
|S
[[A
S
]]
R
defined through
(a|ρ
|S
)
:
= (J
1
S
a|ρ), a [[
¯
A
S
]]. (34)
Defining
ˆ
J
1
S
by duality as
(a|
ˆ
J
1
S
ρ)
:
= (J
1
S
a|ρ), (35)
we can then equivalently express Eq. (34) as
ρ
|S
=
ˆ
J
1
S
ρ. (36)
Representing generalised extended states through
diagrams, and reminding eq. (28), the above
equations can be recast as
ρ
|S
S
a
=
ρ
R
J
1
S
S
a
=
ρ
S
a
G\S
e
,
which can be taken as the definition of the equa-
tion
ρ
|S
S
:
=
ρ
S
G\S
e
. (37)
We can now introduce the set of states [[A
G
]]
as the special set of generalised extended states
whose restrictions are all states. In other words,
an element ρ of the space [[A
G
]]
R
is a state if,
restricted to any finite region R R
(G)
, it defines
a state for that region.
Definition 18 (Extended states). The set [[A
G
]]
of states in the space of generalised extended
states [[A
G
]]
R
is the set of those elements ρ
[[A
G
]]
R
such that for every R R
(G)
the local re-
striction of ρ to R is a state ρ
|R
[[A
R
]]. Deter-
ministic states, whose set is denoted by [[A
G
]]
1
,
are those states ρ [[A
G
]] with (e
G
|ρ) = 1.
One can easily verify that the set [[A
G
]] is con-
vex, as a consequence of convexity of [[A]] for ev-
ery finite system A. As we did for finite systems,
we also define a positive cone generated by [[A
G
]].
Moreover, it is easy to check that the restriciton
of a state to an infinite region S R
(G)
is s state
in [[A
S
]].
Definition 19 (Extended positive cone). The set
[[A
G
]]
+
in the space of generalised extended states
[[A
G
]]
R
is the cone of those elements ρ [[A
G
]]
R
such that there exist ¯ρ [[A
G
]] and µ 0 such
that ρ = µ¯ρ.
We can now show an important result about
the restriction of states.
Lemma 17. The restriction
ˆ
J
1
R
[[A
G
]] of the set
of states of A
G
coincides with [[A
R
]].
Proof. It is a straightforward exercise to verify
that
ˆ
J
1
R
[[A
G
]] [[A
R
]]. For the converse, let
ρ [[A
R
]], and let us now construct a state σ
[[A
G
]] such that σ
|R
= ρ. We define
¯
R
:
= G \ R.
There are two possible situations:
¯
R R
(G)
, or
¯
R R
(G)
. If
¯
R R
(G)
, let a
T
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, with
T R
(G)
. We define
(a|σ)
:
= (a|ρ
|T R
ν
|T
¯
R
), (38)
for an arbitrary ν [[A
¯
R
]], where we introduced
the notation σ
|S
0
for S
0
S R
(G)
, and σ a state
of the composite system σ [[A
S
]] = [[A
S
0
A
S\S
0
]],
with
σ
|S
0
S
0
:
=
σ
S
0
S\S
0
e
.
Clearly, the functional σ is bounded, and thus
it can be extended to a functional on the full
space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, i.e. σ [[A
G
]]
R
. Moreover one can
easily verify that σ
|T
[[A
T
]] for every T R
(G)
,
thus σ is the desired state in [[A
G
]]. A similar
construction can be carried out for the case
¯
R
R
(G)
, taking ν [[A
¯
R
]]. By construction, also in
this case σ [[A
G
]], as can be straightforwardly
checked.
The next result that we prove is that quasi-
local effects a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
are positive on the set
[[A
G
]].
Lemma 18. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
, and ρ [[A
G
]].
Then (a|ρ) 0
Proof. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
be a local effect a
R
=
[a
R
]. Then, by definition, (a
R
|ρ) = (a|ρ
|R
)
0. Now, let a = [a
n
R
n
]. We have (a|ρ) =
lim
n→∞
(a
n
R
n
|ρ) 0.
The following result draws a first analogy be-
tween the properties of the sup-norm for finite
systems and that for infinite parallel composi-
tions.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 20
Lemma 19. Let ρ [[A
G
]]
+
. Then kρk
=
(e
G
|ρ).
Proof. Let ρ [[A
G
]]
+
. Then, by virtue of
lemma 18, (a|ρ) 0 for all a [[
¯
A
G
]]. Let now
kak
sup
= 1. By lemma 15, one has e
G
± a 0,
and thus (e
G
|ρ) |(a|ρ)|. Then (e
G
|ρ) kρk
.
On the other hand, being e
G
a legitimate el-
ement of [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
with ke
G
k
sup
= 1, one has
kρk
= sup
kak
sup
=1
|(a|ρ)| (e
G
|ρ).
Thanks to lemma 12, we have the following
corollary.
Corollary 9. Let ρ [[A
G
]]. Then 0 (a|ρ)
(e
G
|ρ) for every a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
We can now show that also in the infinite case
every state is proportional to a deterministic one.
Let us first prove a preliminary lemma.
Lemma 20. Let ρ [[A
G
]]
R
. If (a|ρ) = 0 for
every a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
, then ρ = 0.
Proof. If (a|ρ) = 0 for every a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
then,
using lemma 11, we have
(2a e
G
|ρ) = (a|ρ) (e
G
a|ρ) = 0, a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
This implies that kρk
= 0, and thus ρ = 0.
Proposition 7. Every state ρ [[A
G
]] is propor-
tional to a deterministic state ¯ρ [[A
G
]]
1
.
Proof. Let ρ [[A
G
]]. If ρ = 0, then for every
¯ρ [[A
G
]]
1
it is ρ = 0¯ρ. Let then ρ 6= 0. By
lemmas 18 and 20, there must exist a [[
¯
A
G
]]
such that (a|ρ) > 0. By corollary 9, one then
has (e
G
|ρ) (a|ρ) > 0. By definition, for every
S R
(G)
, we have
(e
A
S
|ρ
|S
) = (e
S
|ρ) = (e
G
|ρ) > 0.
Thus, if we set ¯ρ
:
= ρ/(e
G
|ρ), for every S R
(G)
we obtain
(e
A
S
|¯ρ
|S
) = (e
G
|¯ρ) = 1,
implying that ¯ρ
|S
[[A
S
]]
1
for every S R
(G)
.
Then, ¯ρ [[A
G
]]
1
, and ¯ρ is such that ρ = (e
G
|ρ)¯ρ.
We now show that the operational norm is
equivalently defined on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
by
kak
op
:
= sup
ρ[[A
G
]]
|(a|ρ)|.
Indeed, let a = [a
nR
n
]. Then
|(a|ρ)| = lim
n→∞
|(a
nR
n
|ρ)| = lim
n→∞
|(a
n
|ρ
|R
n
)|.
This implies that
|(a|ρ)| |(a
n
|ρ
|R
n
)| + ε ka
nR
n
k
op
+ ε,
thus sup
ρ[[A
G
]]
|(a|ρ)| kak
op
. On the other
hand, for every a
nR
n
and every ε, there exists
ρ
ε
[[A
R
n
]] such that ka
nR
n
k
op
|(a
n
|ρ
ε
)| + ε.
Now, by lemma 17, this implies that for every ε
there exists ˜ρ
ε
[[A
G
]] such that
ka
nR
n
k
op
ε |(a
nR
n
|˜ρ
ε
)|.
Finally, this implies that for every ε there exists
ρ
ε
[[A
G
]] such that
kak
op
3ε ka
nR
n
k
op
2ε
|(a
nR
n
|˜ρ
ε
)| ε
|(a|˜ρ
ε
)|. (39)
Thus, in conclusion, kak
op
sup
ρ[[A
G
]]
|(a|ρ)|.
A crucial property of [[A
G
]] is that extended
states are separating for [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
, namely if for ev-
ery state two generalised effects give the same
value, then they coincide.
Theorem 6 (States separate effects). Let a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. If (a|ρ) = 0 for all ρ [[A
G
]]
1
, then
a = 0.
Proof. Let a = [a
n
R
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and (a|ρ) = 0
for every ρ [[A
G
]]
1
. Then for every ρ [[A
G
]]
1
one has
|(a
n
|ρ)| = |(a
n
a|ρ)| ka
n
ak
sup
,
and thus for every ε > 0 there exists n
0
such
that, for n n
0
, ka
n
k
op
ε. Thus, we have
kak
op
= 0. As a consequence, for every ε > 0
there exists n
0
such that for n n
0
one has
ka
n
k
sup
kka
n
k
op
ε,
and thus kak
sup
= 0. Now, this implies that a =
0.
Remark 2. The above result is made possible
by requirement (15) that the sup-norm and the
operational norm for effects of finite systems A
are bounded as
a [[
¯
A]]
R
kak
sup
kkak
op
,
with k independent of the system A. In par-
ticular, this is true under the assumption (16),
i.e. that [[
¯
A]]
+
[[A]]
+
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 21
We can now prove the main consequence of
uniqueness of the deterministic effect e
G
for A
G
,
i.e. that e
G
is the unique effect that amounts to
1 on [[A
G
]]
1
.
Proposition 8. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. Then (a|ρ) = 1
for all ρ [[A
G
]]
1
if and only if a = e
G
.
Proof. Notice that, since e
G
a for every a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
, and (b|ρ) 0 for every b [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
and
ρ [[A
G
]]
1
, we have
0 (e
G
a|ρ) = 1 (a|ρ),
which implies (a|ρ) 1 for every ρ [[A
G
]]
1
.
Now, if (a|ρ) = 1 for every ρ [[A
G
]]
1
, we have
(e
G
a|ρ) = 0, ρ [[A
G
]]
1
,
which by theorem 6 implies a = e
G
.
A class of states of particular interest is that
of quasi-local states, which are intuitively under-
stood as states whose preparation can be arbi-
trarily approximated by local procedures. These
live in small subspaces of the space [[A
G
]]
R
. Their
construction is similar to that of quasi-local ef-
fects, but differs form it in a relevant respect,
that is the necessity of defining arbitrary refer-
ence states. The construction is inspired by pio-
neering works on infinite tensor products by von
Neumann and Murray [49], and can be found in
appendix B.
4.3 Quasi-local transformations
Now we are going to define the quasi-local alge-
bra [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
of transformations. In usual
approaches to quantum infinite systems, one usu-
ally introduces the effect algebra, that in the OPT
case would correspond to the space of quasi-local
effects. However, one can easily understand that,
unlike effects in a general OPT, the quantum ef-
fect algebra contains far more information than
the mere structure of the space of effects. Indeed,
in the quantum effect algebra one can find every
operator on the Hilbert space, and in turn, the
operational role of a linear operator is to provide a
Kraus representation of a transformation. In this
perspective, one can also understand why mul-
tiplication of effects has a meaning at all: there
is no point in multiplying effects, but multiplica-
tion of Kraus operators is the mathematical rep-
resentation of sequential composition. Thus, the
algebraic structure of effects conveniently sum-
marises information about every kind of event in
the theory: effects, with their coarse-graining rep-
resented by the sum, and transformations, with
sequential composition represented by multiplica-
tion.
Cellular automata are defined in quantum the-
ory by specifying their action on the effect alge-
bra. Such an action thus provides information
about how both effects and transformations are
transformed by the cellular automaton. For a
general OPT, however, such a compact algebraic
structure embodying all the relevant information
is absent, and the definition of a CA on the space
of effects is not sufficient: we need to specify how
the CA transforms transformations.
For these reasons we construct now the Banach
algebra of quasi-local transformations, in a way
that is very closely reminiscent of the construc-
tion of quasi-local effects. Here, in order to define
a local transformation, we recur to the notion of a
transformation that acts non-trivially on finitely
many systems, while it acts as the identity on the
remaining ones. In other words, the role that is
played by the deterministic effect in the case of
local effects is played here by the identity trans-
formation. Also in this case, the topological clo-
sure will be taken in the sup-norm, and this choice
is of great relevance to ensure a Banach algebra
structure for the closure.
Let us then introduce the Banach algebra of
quasi-local transformations.
Definition 20. Let R G be an arbitrary finite
region of G. We define local transformation A
R
of A
G
any pair (A , R), where A [[A
R
A
R
]]
R
.
The action A
R
of A
R
on Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
is defined as
follows
R\S
A
R
a
S
RS
S\R
:
=
R\S
A
R
R\S
e
RS RS
a
S
S\R
. (40)
We also define Pre[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
as the set of
local transformations A
R
.
Lemma 21. Let a
S
b
T
. Then A
R
a
S
A
R
b
T
.
Proof. By hypothesis, there exists c [[
¯
A
ST
]]
R
such that
a = c e
S\T
, b = c e
T \S
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 22
Then we have
(A
R
a
S
| = (c e
S\T
e
R\S
|(A I
S\R
),
(A
R
b
T
| = (c e
T \S
e
R\T
|(A I
T \R
).
By Eq. (10) the thesis follows.
We can now define an equivalence relation be-
tween local transformations as follows
A
S
B
T
(
A = C I
S\T
,
B = C I
T \S
,
(41)
for some C [[A
ST
]]
R
. The set of local transfor-
mations is then defined as
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
:
= Pre[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
/
Lemma 22. Let A
R
Pre[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
. Then
for every finite region H R
(G)
such that H
R = , one has (A I
A
H
)
RH
Pre[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
, and (A I
A
H
)
RH
A
R
.
Proof. It is straightforward to verify that (A
I
A
H
)
RH
A
R
by direct inspection of the defin-
ing equation (41).
We can now provide a way to identify a canon-
ical representative of the equivalence class of A
R
,
which is defined in analogy to the case of effects
as follows.
Definition 21. The minimal representative of
the equivalence class A
R
, denoted as
˜
A
R
A
, is de-
fined through
R
A
:
=
\
SR
(A ,R)
S,
˜
A
R
A
A
R
, (42)
where R
(A ,R)
is the set of all those finite regions
S G for which there exists B [[A
S
A
S
]]
R
such that B
S
A
R
.
Lemma 23. The minimal representative exists
and is unique.
The proof follows step by step that of
lemma 73.
The first result that we need to prove is the
following.
Lemma 24. Let A
R
B
S
. Then for every ef-
fect a
T
Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, one has
A
R
a
T
B
S
a
T
. (43)
Proof. If (
˜
C )
R
C
is the minimal representative of
A
R
B
S
, by Eq. (41), one has
A =
˜
C I
R\R
C
,
B =
˜
C I
S\R
C
.
Now, by the defining equation 40, we have that
(A
R
a
T
| = (˜a e
(T R)\R
a
|(
˜
C I
(T R)\R
C
)
=(˜a e
[T (RS)]\R
a
|(
˜
C I
[T (RS)]\R
C
)
(e
R\S
|,
(B
S
a
T
| = (˜a e
(T S)\R
a
|(
˜
C I
(T S)\R
C
)
=(˜a e
[T (RS)]\R
a
|(
˜
C I
[T (RS)]\R
C
)
(e
S\R
|,
and finally by Eq. (123) this implies the thesis.
By virtue of lemmas 21 and 24, we can define
the action of A
R
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
on local effects
[[
¯
A
G
]]
R
as
A
R
[a
T
]
:
= [A
R
a
T
],
where we leave the square braces to denote equiv-
alence classes for in Pre[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, for the sake of
clarity. We can now make local transformations
into a vector space as we did for local effects, as
follows.
Definition 22. Let A
R
, B
S
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
,
and h R. Then we define
hA
R
:
=
(
(hA )
R
h 6= 0,
0
h = 0,
A
R
+ B
S
:
= C
RS
C
:
= A I
S\R
+ B I
R\S
.
Moreover, the following operation makes the
set of local transformations into an algebra.
Definition 23. Let A
R
, B
S
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
.
Then we define
A
R
B
S
:
= ({A I
S\R
}{B I
R\S
})
RS
.
We omit the straightforward proof that the
above definition is well defined, i.e. independent
of the choice of representatives in the classes of
A
R
and B
S
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 23
Definition 24. The algebra of generalized lo-
cal transformations is the unital algebra [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
of finite real combinations of local trans-
formations, with unit 1
and null element 0
.
In order to close the algebra of local operations
we introduce the topology given by the sup-norm,
given in the following, in analogy to the case of
effects. We also discuss the interplay of the sup-
norm topology with that given by the operational
norm, that we define right away.
Definition 25. The operational norm kA
R
k
op
of
˜
A
R
A
= A
R
[[A A]]
LR
is defined by the
following expression
kA
R
k
op
:
= k
˜
A k
op
. (44)
Proposition 9. Let A
R
[[A A]]
LR
. Then
kA
R
k
op
= kA k
op
.
Proof. Let A
R
˜
A
R
A
, and let R = R
A
R
0
,
with R
A
R
0
= . Then by Eq. (41) we have
A =
˜
A I
A
R
0
,
Now, by definition of k·k
op
(see [8]) it straightfor-
wardly follows that kB I
C
k
op
= kBk
op
. Thus,
kA
R
k
op
= k
˜
A k
op
= kA k
op
.
Unfortunately, the operational norm does not
enjoy the basic property that would make the al-
gebra of transformations into a Banach algebra,
i.e. it is not true that kA Bk
op
kA k
op
kBk
op
.
For this reason, in analogy with the case of quasi-
local effects, we introduce a second norm, the sup-
norm, whose interplay with the operational norm
will make it possible to define the closed Banach
algebra of quasi-local transformations.
This is obtained extending the definition of
sup-norm to the algebra of local transformations
of A
G
.
Definition 26. The sup-norm kA
R
k
sup
of A
R
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
is defined as
kA
R
k
sup
:
= inf J(
˜
A ) = k
˜
A k
sup
. (45)
Proposition 10. Let A
R
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
.
Then kA
R
k
sup
= kA k
sup
.
Proof. Let A
R
˜
A
R
A
, and let R = R
A
R
0
,
with R
A
R
0
= . Then by Eq. (41) we have
A =
˜
A I
A
R
0
,
and by corollary 2, kA k
sup
= k
˜
A k
sup
=
kA
R
k
sup
.
Corollary 10. Let A , B [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
.
Then kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
.
Proof. The result is a straightforward conse-
quence of propositions 10 and 2.
Corollary 11. On [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
, one has
kA
R
k
op
kA
R
k
sup
.
Proof. The result is a straightforward conse-
quence of propositions 9 and 10, and corol-
lary 4.
The above results allow us to extend the lo-
cal algebra of events into the quasi-local alge-
bra, which is a Banach algebra. The construc-
tion is analogous to that of quasi-local states, and
proceeds as follows. First we define the algebra
[[A
G
A
G
]]
CR
of sup-Cauchy sequences of local
transformations, i.e. its elements are sequences
A : N [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
:: n 7→ A
n
R
n
such that
for every ε > 0 there exists n
0
N such that
for all m, n n
0
, one has kA
n
A
m
k
sup
< ε.
Now we define the equivalence relation between
elements of [[A
G
A
G
]]
CR
: A
=
B if for every
ε > 0 there exists n
0
N such that for every
n n
0
one has kA
n
B
n
k
sup
< ε. Finally, we
define the quasi-local algebra as follows.
Definition 27. The space of quasi-local trans-
formations of A is defined as
[[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
:
= [[A
G
A
G
]]
CR
/
=
.
Definition 28. An element A in [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
is an event if A = [A
nR
n
] for a sequence A
nR
n
such that A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]] for all n N. The
set of events will be denoted by [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
An element A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
is a channel
if A = [A
n
R
n
] for a sequence A
n
R
n
such that
A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]]
1
for all n N. The set of
channels will be denoted by [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
.
The subset of [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
containing ele-
ments A = [A
n
R
n
] for a sequence A
n
R
n
such
that A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]]
+
for all n N will be
denoted by [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
. Equivalently, we will
write A 0 for A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
In the following, in analogy with the finite case,
we will write A B if A B 0. The algebra
of quasi-local transformations [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
is
defined as follows.
Definition 29. Let A = [A
n
R
n
], B = [B
n
S
n
].
We define A B
:
= [A
n
R
n
B
n
S
n
].
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 24
The product A B is well defined. Indeed:
1. A
n
R
n
B
n
S
n
is a Cauchy sequence.
2. For every A
0
n
R
0
n
, B
0
n
S
0
n
in the equivalence
classes defining A and B, respectively, one
has A
n
R
n
B
n
S
n
=
A
0
n
R
0
n
B
0
n
S
0
n
.
Item 1 can be easily proved since we have
kA
n
B
n
A
m
B
m
k
sup
=kA
n
B
n
A
m
B
n
+ A
m
B
n
A
m
B
m
k
sup
≤kA
n
A
m
k
sup
kB
n
k
sup
+ kA
m
k
sup
kB
n
B
m
k
sup
.
Similarly, for item 2 we have
kA
n
B
n
A
0
n
B
0
n
k
sup
=kA
n
B
n
A
0
n
B
n
+ A
0
n
B
n
A
0
n
B
0
n
k
sup
≤kA
n
A
0
n
k
sup
kB
n
k
sup
+ kA
0
n
k
sup
kB
n
B
0
n
k
sup
.
The quasi-local algebra is actually a real Ba-
nach algebra if equipped with the norm k·k
sup
, as
we now prove.
Proposition 11. The algebra [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
equipped with the norm k·k
sup
is a Banach al-
gebra.
Proof. We only need to prove that kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
. Let A = [A
n
R
n
] and B =
[B
n
S
n
], respectively. Now, for every A
n
R
n
and
B
n
S
n
one has
k(A
n
I
S
n
\R
n
)(B
n
I
R
n
\S
n
)k
sup
kA
n
I
S
n
\R
n
k
sup
kB
n
I
R
n
\S
n
k
sup
,
and by proposition 10 kA Bk
sup
kA k
sup
kBk
sup
.
The subsets [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
and [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
are convex, and [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
is a convex cone.
Moreover, they are closed in the sup-norm.
Proposition 12. The sets [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
,
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
, and [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
are closed
in the sup-norm.
Proof. The argument is the same in both cases.
Let {A
m
}
mN
be a Cauchy sequence with
A
m
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
for all m, with =
“nothing”, 1, +. By definition, A
m
= [A
mnR
mn
],
with A
mn
[[A
R
mn
A
R
mn
]]
. Then one eas-
ily proves that the sequence {A
mmR
mm
}
mN
is
Cauchy, and its limit is A
:
= lim
m→∞
A
mmR
mm
,
which by definition is in [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proposition 13. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. Then
kA k
op
kA k
sup
. (46)
Proof. By definition kA k
op
= lim
n→∞
kA
n
k
op
and kA k
sup
= lim
n→∞
kA
n
k
sup
, where
{A
n
R
n
}
nN
[[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
is a Cauchy
sequence converging to A , thus by proposition 3
one has
kA
n
k
op
kA
n
k
sup
, n N,
which implies the inequality in the limit.
Now, we can prove the following lemma.
Lemma 25. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
be a Cauchy se-
quence, and let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
. We then
have
A
a [[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
. (47)
Proof. We just need to evaluate
kA
a
m
A
a
n
k
sup
, and using proposition 2 one
has
kA
(a
m
a
n
)k
sup
ka
m
a
n
k
sup
kA k
sup
.
Since the sequence a is Cauchy, also A
a is
Cauchy.
Lemma 26. Let a, b [[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
be equivalent
Cauchy sequences, and let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
.
We then have
[A
a
nR
n
] = [A
b
nS
n
]. (48)
Proof. We can bound kA
a
n
A
b
n
k
sup
using
proposition 2, obtaining
kA
(a
n
b
n
)k
sup
ka
n
b
n
k
sup
kA k
sup
.
Since [a
nR
n
] = [b
nS
n
], the thesis follows.
As a consequence of the above results, all local
transformations leave the space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
invari-
ant. We now prove a further important result:
the above statement can be extended to all the
quasi-local algebra.
Theorem 7. The quasi-local algebra [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
leaves the space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
invariant, and
for every A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
and every a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, it is
kA
ak
sup
kak
sup
kA k
sup
. (49)
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 25
Proof. By proposition 2 and lemma 25, the thesis
is true for A [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
and a [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
.
Let now a = [a
pR
p
] and A [[A
G
A
G
]]
LR
.
Then
kA
a
p
k
sup
ka
p
k
sup
kA k
sup
,
and taking the limit for p we obtain the
thesis. Finally, let A = [A
nR
n
]. In this case,
by lemma 25 A
n
a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
for every n N.
Moreover, {A
n
a}
nN
[[
¯
A
G
]]
CR
. Indeed, by the
result we just proved
k(A
n
A
m
)ak
sup
kak
sup
kA
n
A
m
k
sup
.
Finally, by lemma 25, we have
kA
n
ak
sup
kak
sup
kA
n
k
sup
,
and taking the limit for n we obtain the
thesis.
A remarkable result that will be important in
the following is given by the following lemma.
Lemma 27. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
. Then for
every a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
one has A
a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. By hypothesis, A = [A
nR
n
] and a =
[a
mS
m
], with A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]] and a
m
[[
¯
A
S
m
]]. Thus A
n
a
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
S
n
]]. Now, one can
easily verify that lim
n→∞
A
n
a
n
= A
a, which
proves the statement.
In particular, one has the following condition.
Lemma 28. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
. Then
A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
iff A
e
G
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. By definition, one has A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
if and only if A = [A
nR
n
] with A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]], and by our assumptions the latter is equiv-
alent to a
n
:
= A
n
e
A
R
n
[[
¯
A
R
n
]]. Now, since
ka
nR
n
a
mR
m
k
sup
kA
nR
n
A
mR
m
k
sup
, one
has that A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
if and only if
A
e
G
= [a
nR
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
.
Lemma 29. Let A [[A B]]
Q+
, and a
:
=
A
e
G
. Then kA k
sup
= kak
sup
.
Proof. By definition, A = [A
nR
n
], with A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]]
+
. Now, kA
n
R
n
k
sup
= kA
n
k
sup
,
and by lemma 7, kA
n
k
sup
= kA
n
e
R
n
k
sup
=
kA
nR
n
e
G
k
sup
. Then,
kA k
sup
= lim
n→∞
kA
n
R
n
e
G
k
sup
= kA
e
G
k
sup
.
On the same line, we can provide the following
condition for A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
to be a channel.
Lemma 30. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
. Then
A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
iff A
e
G
= e
G
.
Proof. First, let A be a channel. By definition
it must be A = lim
n→∞
A
nR
n
, where A
nR
n
are
local channels. Thus, by theorem 3, A
nR
n
e
G
=
e
G
. It follows that A
e
G
= lim
n→∞
A
nR
n
e
G
=
e
G
. Now, for the converse, by definition A
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
iff A = [A
n
R
n
] with A
n
R
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]]
+
for all n N. Let us take n n
0
so that kA
n
R
n
A k
sup
ε. Then we have
|kA
n
R
n
k
sup
kA k
sup
| ε.
Now, by lemma 29, since A
e
G
= e
G
, we
have kA k
sup
= 1. Let us define A
0
n
R
n
:
=
A
n
R
n
/kA
n
R
n
k
sup
. Clearly,
kA
0
n
R
n
A
n
R
n
k
sup
= kA
n
R
n
k
sup
|1 1/kA
n
R
n
k
sup
| ε.
This implies that A
0
n
R
n
is a sequence converg-
ing to A , with kA
0
n
R
n
k
sup
= 1. As a con-
sequence, there exist channels C
nR
n
such that
(C
n
A
0
n
)
R
n
0. Again by lemma 7,
k(C
n
A
0
n
)
R
n
k
sup
= k(C
n
A
0
n
)
R
n
e
R
n
k
sup
= ke
G
A
0
n
R
n
e
G
k
sup
= k(A A
0
nR
n
)
e
G
k
sup
k(A A
0
n
R
n
)k
sup
ε.
This implies that A = [A
0
nR
n
] = [C
n
R
n
], and
then A [[A
G
A
G
]]
1
.
The following weak version of the converse of
lemma 28 can be easily proved.
Lemma 31. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
. Then there exists
A [[A
G
]]
LR
such that
a = A
e
G
. (50)
Moreover, for a [[
¯
A
G
]]
L
, Eq. (50) is satisfied
with A [[A
G
A
G
]]
L
.
Proof. Let a = a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
. Let us define
A
R
:
= |σ)(a|, where σ [[A
R
]]
1
is an arbitrary
deterministic state. Then clearly
A
R
e
G
= a
R
.
It is also clear that, for a = a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
L
,
the above defined transformation A
R
is in
[[A
G
]]
L
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 26
One can take a further step, and prove the fol-
lowing result that will be of crucial importance in
the remainder.
Corollary 12. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. Then there
exists a sequence of quasi-local transformations
A
nR
n
such that lim
n→∞
A
nR
n
e
G
= a. If a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
the sequence can be found in [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
Notice that the sequence A
n
R
n
is not necessar-
ily Cauchy, thus one cannot conclude that for ev-
ery a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
there is A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
such
that a = A
e
G
. However, the following lemma
completes the picture.
Proposition 14. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. Then there
exists A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
such that
a = A
e
G
. (51)
Moreover, for a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
with
{“nothing”,1,+} one can find the above A in the
set [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. Let us define the sets
T
ε
a
:
= {A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
| kA
e
G
ak
sup
ε}.
The sets T
ε
a
are not empty for every a and every
ε > 0, as a consequence of corollary 12. More-
over, they are closed. Indeed, let {A
n
}
nN
be a
Cauchy sequence in T
ε
a
. This implies that by defi-
nition a
n
:
= A
n
e
G
¯
B
ε
(a). Since the ball
¯
B
ε
(a)
is closed, also lim
n→∞
a
n
= (lim
n→∞
A
n
)
e
G
¯
B
ε
(a), namely lim
n→∞
A
n
T
ε
a
. Finally, one
clearly has that for ε < δ it is T
ε
a
T
δ
a
, and the
diameter d
ε
:
= sup{kA Bk
sup
| A , B T
ε
a
} is
a non-decreasing function of ε. Let then
T
0
a
:
=
\
ε>0
T
ε
a
.
Either lim
ε0
+
d
ε
> 0, in which case T
0
a
is non
empty, and each of its elements satisfies A
e
g
=
a, or the limit is 0, in which case, by Cantor’s
intersection theorem for complete metric spaces,
T
0
a
= {A } is a singleton, with A
e
G
= a. The
same argument can be applied in each of the cases
where a [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
, considering the closed sets
T
ε
a
:
= T
ε
a
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
We now prove a result that is analogous to
lemma 12.
Lemma 32. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
, and
C A [[
¯
A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
for some C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
. Then A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
Proof. By definition, there are three sequences
A
nR
n
, A
0
nS
n
in [[A
G
A
G
]]
L
and C
nT
n
in [[A
G
A
G
]]
L1
such that lim
n→∞
A
n
= A , lim
n→∞
A
0
n
=
C A , and lim
n→∞
C
n
= C . This implies that
kC
n
(A
n
+ A
0
n
)k
sup
ε,
and consequently there is a sequence of channels
D
n
in [[A
G
A
G
]]
L1
such that
εD
n
+ C
n
(A
n
+ A
0
n
) 0.
By the above equation, it is easy to check that
F
n
1
1 + ε
A
n
0, F
n
1
1 + ε
A
0
n
0,
where F
n
is the channel ε/(1+ε)D
n
+1/(1+ε)C
n
.
Thus, by theorem 5, both A
n
/(1+ε) and A
0
n
/(1+
ε) belong to [[A
G
A
G
]]
L
. Let ε
m
be a real
Cauchy sequence converging to 0, and consider
the corresponding sequences B
m
:
= A
n
m
/(1 +
ε
m
), B
0
m
:
= A
0
n
m
/(1 + ε
m
). Since
kB
m
A
n
m
k
sup
=
ε
m
1 + ε
m
kA
n
m
k
sup
,
kB
0
m
A
0
n
m
k
sup
=
ε
m
1 + ε
m
kA
0
n
m
k
sup
,
one has A = [A
nR
n
] = [B
mR
m
] and C A =
[A
0
nS
n
] = [B
0
mS
m
], with B
n
and B
0
n
beloning to
[[A
G
A
G
]]
L
. Thus, A , C A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
We will now define the action of the quasi-local
algebra of transformations on quasi-local states.
The action is defined by duality as follows.
Definition 30 (Dual action of the quasi-local
algebra). Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. We define the
map
ˆ
A : [[A
G
]]
R
[[A
G
]]
R
as follows
(a|
ˆ
A ρ)
:
= (A
a|ρ), a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. (52)
The first thing we need to prove is that the
map
ˆ
A : [[A
G
]]
R
[[A
G
]]
R
is linear and bounded.
Proposition 15. For every A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
the map
ˆ
A : [[A
G
]]
R
[[A
G
]]
R
is linear and
bounded.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 27
Proof. As to linearity, it is sufficient to consider
that
(a|
ˆ
A [
1
+ yρ
2
]) = (A
a|
1
+ yρ
2
)
= x(A
a|ρ
1
) + y(A
a|ρ
2
)
= (a|x
ˆ
A ρ
1
) + (a|y
ˆ
A ρ
2
),
which by definition implies
ˆ
A (
1
+ yρ
2
) = x
ˆ
A ρ
1
+ y
ˆ
A ρ
2
.
In order to prove boundedness, it is sufficient to
consider Eq. (49), to conclude that
|(a|
ˆ
A ρ)| = |(A
a|ρ)| kA
ak
sup
kρk
kak
sup
kA k
sup
kρk
,
which implies that
k
ˆ
A ρk
kA k
sup
kρk
.
We now prove that [[A
G
]]
QR
is invariant under
the quasi-local algebra, and more precisely, every
space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
is invariant.
Theorem 8. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. Then
ˆ
A [[A
G
]]
QR
[[A
G
]]
QR
,
and for every (B, ρ
0
),
ˆ
A [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
.
Proof. We start observing that, by Eq. (40),
when we apply A
R
a
S
to a local state τ
T
in
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
, we obtain
A
R
A
(RS)\T
A
S\(RT )
A
R\(ST )
A
RST
A
(RT )\S
A
T \(RS)
A
(T S)\R
ρ
0(RS)\T
τ
T
a
S
e
e
e
,
for every S and every a
S
[[
¯
A
S
]]
R
, which implies
ˆ
A
R
τ
T
A
B(R\T )
A
RT
A
S\R
(53)
=
ρ
0B(R\T )
A
B(R\T )\(R\T )
A
R\T
A
R
A
R\T
τ
T
A
RT
A
RT
A
T \R
.
This means that local states in [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
are
mapped to local states in the same sector un-
der
ˆ
A
R
. Now, by proposition 15, Cauchy se-
quences are mapped to Cauchy sequences, so that
ˆ
A
R
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. Moreover, again by
proposition 15, also Cauchy sequences of local
transformations satisfy the same condition, thus
ˆ
A [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. Similarly, one can eas-
ily prove that
ˆ
A [[A
G
]]
QR
[[A
G
]]
QR
.
As a consequence of the above theorem, the ac-
tion of [[A A]]
Q
on the space [[A
G
]]
QR
of quasi-
local states is decomposed into many irreducible
representations, one for every space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
.
Remark 3. Notice that, given A , B [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
, one has
(A B)
= B
A
,
\
(A B) =
ˆ
A
ˆ
B. (54)
Let R R
(G)
, and let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
.
Suppose that A = [A
mR
m
] and for every m N,
RR
m
= . This implies that, for S
m
= R
m
R,
A = [A
0
mS
m
], with A
0
mS
m
= (A
m
I
R
)
S
m
, for
A
0
m
[[A
S
m
\R
]]
R
. We then write A = B I
R
.
Notice that in this case, given ρ [[A
G
]]
R
, one has
kρ
|R
(
ˆ
A ρ)
|R
k
op
= k(
ˆ
A
m
ρ)
|R
(
ˆ
A ρ)
|R
k
op
k(
ˆ
A
m
ˆ
A )ρk
εkρk
,
and then (
ˆ
A ρ)
|R
= ρ
|R
.
For R R
(G)
, there is a straightforward
ordered Banach algebra isomorphism between
[[A
R
A
R
]]
QR
and [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
, where the
latter is defined as
[[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
:
= {A
R
| A [[A
R
A
R
]]
R
}.
A similar isomorphism can be found also in the
case of infinite regions R R
(G)
, where by defi-
nition [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
is the closed subalgebra
of Cauchy classes [A
n
R
n
] with R
n
R for every
n N. The isomorphism in this case is given by
[[A
R
A
R
]]
QR
= J
R
[[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
J
1
R
,
(55)
where J
R
: [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
R
]]
QR
is defined in
Eq. (25). In the following, when we want to spec-
ify that a given quasi-local transformation A is
in the subalgebra [[A
R
A
R
]]
QR
, we will write
A
R
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 28
Remark 4. Notice that every quasi-local trans-
formation in [[A
R
A
R
]]
QR
does not only rep-
resent a linear map on [[
¯
A
R
]]
QR
, but a family of
maps that represent the same transformation act-
ing on [[
¯
A
G
]] for every R G. This is due to the
isomorphism of [[A
R
A
R
]]
QR
with the subalge-
bra [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
given in Eq. (55).
The following result shows that [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
preserves the subspace [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
.
Lemma 33. Let A [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
. Then
A
[[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
.
Proof. Let A
nR
n
be a sequence in the class of
A , with R
n
R for every n. Let a
mS
m
be a
sequence in the class of a [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
, with S
m
R for all m. Then A
a = [(A
n
a
n
)
R
n
S
n
], and
for every n, R
n
S
n
R. This implies that
A
a [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
.
The following intuitive result states that an ef-
fect that is localised in the region R G is ob-
tained by a quasi-local transformation that is lo-
calised in the same region. This has a straight-
forward proof that will be omitted.
Lemma 34. Let a [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
Q
, with
{“nothing”, 1, +, R}. Then
a = A
e
G
,
with A [[A
(G)
R
A
(G)
R
]]
Q
.
We conclude the section with a result that con-
firms, under restrictive hypotheses, an obvious
expectation.
Lemma 35. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. Then
kA k
sup
= inf J(A ), where
J(A )
:
= {λ R | C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
, λC ± A 0}.
Proof. Let λ J(A ). Then there exists a quasi-
local channel C such that λC ± A 0. By defi-
nition, this implies that λC ± A = [B
±
nR
±
n
] with
B
±
0. Defining A
n
:
= 1/2(B
+
n
B
n
) and
C
n
:
= 1/(2λ)(B
+
n
+ B
n
), by construction one
has
[C
nS
+
n
] = C , [A
nS
n
] = A ,
where the domains S
±
n
are suitably defined. On
the other hand, C = [D
nT
n
] for D
nT
n
[[A
T
n
A
T
n
]]
1
. Thus, one has kC
n
D
n
k
sup
ε, taking
suitable care in defining the domain U
n
:
= S
+
n
T
n
of C
n
D
n
. In other terms, one can find a
channel F
n
such that
εF
n
+ D
n
C
n
0,
εF
n
D
n
+ C
n
0.
In turn, this implies that
(1 + ε)e
U
n
c
n
0,
(ε 1)e
U
n
+ c
n
0,
where c
n
:
= C
n
e
U
n
. Considering the first of the
above relations, we can define
G
n
:
=
1
1 + ε
C
n
+ |ρ
n
)(d
n
|,
where d
n
:
= e
U
n
1/(1 + ε)c
n
0 and ρ
n
is an
arbitrary state in [[A
U
n
]]
1
. By our assumptions,
since G
n
0 and G
n
e
U
n
= e
U
n
, G
n
is a channel.
Moreover, by construction we have that
λ(1 + ε)G
n
± A
n
= B
±
n
+ λ(1 + ε)|ρ
n
)(d
n
| 0,
thus λ(1 + ε) J(A
n
), i.e. λ(1 + ε) kA
n
k
sup
.
In the limit, we then have λ kA k
sup
. On the
other hand, if λ 6∈ J(A ), for every C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
one has
λC + A 6 0 λC A 6 0. (56)
Since the sequence λC ±A
n
converges to λC ±A
for every sequence A
n
converging to A , and the
positive cone is closed, for every C and every A
n
as above, there must be n
0
such that for n n
0
λC + A
n
6 0 λC A
n
6 0. (57)
This holds, in particular, for every local C
n
with
the same domain as A
n
, which implies λ 6∈
J(A
n
). As a consequence, λ < kA
n
k
sup
, and
finally λ kA k
sup
. It is now easy to conclude
that inf J(A ) = kA k
sup
.
We now prove that the infimum defining the
sup norm is actually a minimum, analogously to
the case of effects. The proof in this case is less
straightforward, and we first need the following
lemma.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 29
Lemma 36. Given A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
, let
S
λ
A
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
be the set of channels C
such that λC ± A 0. Then S
λ
A
is closed in the
sup-norm.
Proof. The empty set is closed, so we will con-
sider the case where S
λ
A
is not empty. Let
{C
n
}
nN
be a Cauchy sequence in S
λ
A
. Then
D
±
n
:
= λC
n
± A 0 are both Cauchy sequences,
that by definition converge to λC ± A 0. By
proposition 12, C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
.
Proposition 16. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. Then
there exists a quasi local channel C such that
kA k
sup
C ± A 0. (58)
Proof. By lemma 35, for every ε > 0 there exists
C
ε
such that (kA k
sup
+ε)C
ε
±A 0. Let us then
consider the non empty sets S
ε
:
= S
kA k
sup
+ε
A
, that
are closed by lemma 36. It is straightforward to
verify that for δ < ε it is S
δ
S
ε
. Let d
ε
be the
diameter of S
ε
, namely d
ε
:
= sup{kC
1
C
2
k
sup
|
C
1
, C
2
S
ε
}. Notice that 0 d
ε
2. Being
d
ε
a non-decreasing function of ε, d
0
= lim
ε0
+
exists. The limit d
0
is the diameter of
S
0
:
=
\
ε>0
S
ε
.
If d
0
> 0, then S
0
is clearly not empty, and each of
its elements is a channel C such that kA k
sup
C ±
A 0. If d
0
= 0, then by Cantor’s intersection
theorem for complete metric spaces the set S
0
is
a singleton S
0
= {C
}, with kA k
sup
C
± A
0.
We finally prove a crucial result, that is the
converse of lemma 32. This shows that every
quasi-local event is an element of a quasi-local
test.
Proposition 17. Let A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Then A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
if and only if there
exists C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
such that C A
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q+
.
Proof. Sufficiency is proved in lemma 32. Let us
then prove that if A [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
then there
exists C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
such that C A 0.
First of all, notice that A = [A
nR
n
] with A
n
[[A
R
n
A
R
n
]], and then by
kA k
sup
= lim
n→∞
kA
n
k
sup
= lim
n→∞
kA
nR
n
e
G
k
sup
1.
By proposition 16, there exists C [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
such that
C A kA k
sup
C A 0.
5 Global update rules
We have now set the theoretical background
needed for the definition of a cellular automaton.
In the present section we give the definition of
an update rule (UR), that along with the system
A
G
—the array of cells, whose definition has been
analyzed in detail in the previous sections—will
provide the backbone of the notion of a cellu-
lar automaton. We then introduce the notion of
a global update rule (GUR), as a family of up-
date rules satisfying suitable admissibility condi-
tions in order to represent a local action when
extended to composite systems A
G
C. A GUR
thus describes the evolution occurring when we
apply the global update rule on a joint state of
A
G
and C, leaving C unaffected. We then analyse
the main features of GURs, and in particular we
focus on the causal influence relation given by a
global update rule, and the block decomposition
that allows one to calculate the action of a GUR
on local effects using only local transformations.
Remark 5. In the remainder we will assume
that for every g G the system A
g
is not trivial,
namely A
g
6' I.
First of all let V
be a bounded automorphism
of the space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
of quasi-local effects. Then,
with a notation that is reminiscent of the one
adopted for quasi-local transformations, we will
denote its action as
V
: [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
:: a 7→ V
a.
The action on effects allows us to define the dual
map that acts on the space of extended states, as
follows
(a|
ˆ
V ρ)
:
= (V
a|ρ), a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. (59)
One can easily verify that
ˆ
V is linear and
bounded, thanks to boundedness of the map V
.
Unlike the usual notion of a map in quantum the-
ory or theories with local discriminability, how-
ever, the action of
ˆ
V or V
is not sufficient to
identify uniquely the corresponding transforma-
tion. In particular, those actions are not suffi-
cient to determine that of V I
C
, when sys-
tem A
G
is considered as a part of the composite
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 30
system A
G
C. For this reason we need to define
an automorphic transformation of [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
with
care. One further delicate issue is the follow-
ing. When one conjugates a quasi-local transfor-
mation A with an automorphism V
, obtianing
A
0
= V
1
A V
, the latter is a linear bounded
map on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, but there is no guarantee that
it is still an element of the quasi-local algebra
[[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
, which is surely a desideratum for
candidate cellular automata. In the remainder,
when we write A
G
C we mean to deal with a sys-
tem A
G
0
with G
0
= G h
0
and A
h
0
=
C. In
view of the above observations, we introduce the
following notion
Definition 31 (Automorphic family). An auto-
morphic family of maps on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
is a collec-
tion of automorphisms V
C
of [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
QR
, one for
every C Sys(Θ), with the properties i) for every
A [[A
C
A
C
]]
R
one has V
1
C
A
h
0
V
C
= A
h
0
;
ii) for fixed C
0
and every choice of system C
1
,
setting C = C
0
C
1
and A
G
0
:
= A
G
C
0
, and for ev-
ery A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
, there exist A
0
, A
00
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
such that
V
1
C
A
G
0
V
C
= A
0†
G
0
, (60)
A
G
0
= V
C
A
00†
G
0
V
1
C
, (61)
where A
0†
= (V
1
C
0
A
V
C
0
), and A
00†
=
(V
1
C
0
A
V
C
0
)
We remark that, as a special case of item ii)
in definition 31, taking C
0
I and C = C
1
, for
every choice of system C, and every A [[A
G
]]
QR
,
one has
V
1
C
A
G
V
C
= (V
1
I
A
G
V
I
)
G
,
V
C
A
G
V
1
C
= (V
I
A
G
V
1
I
)
G
.
When referring to an automorphic family we
will use the shorthand V
. One has to remind,
however, that this symbol refers to a family of
automorphisms. In particular, the definition is
meant to allow for formulas such as V A V
1
,
V [[A
G
A
G
]]
$
V
1
, for $ = Q, L and =
R, +, 1 or nothing. The meaning of the two ex-
pressions above is given by the following defini-
tions:
V A V
1
:
= {
ˆ
V
C
0
C
(
ˆ
A
ˆ
I
C
)
ˆ
V
1
C
0
C
| C Sys(Θ)},
(62)
V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
$
V
1
:
=
{V A V
1
| A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
$
}. (63)
Notice that by definition of an automorphic fam-
ily and by Eq. (62), one has
V A V
1
= {(
ˆ
V
C
0
ˆ
A
ˆ
V
1
C
0
)
ˆ
I
C
| C Sys(Θ)},
(64)
namely an automorphic family maps [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
onto itself surjectively. In particular, this
is true of [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
. This implies that for
A [[A
G
C A
G
C]]
QR
, V A V
1
represents a
quasi-local transformation in [[A
G
C A
G
C]]
QR
.
An automorphic family is defined as to satisfy
some necessary conditions that we require for the
representatives of a transformation of the form
V I
C
. However, the definition of an automor-
phic family is not sufficient to ensure consistency.
This fact must be taken into account in the next
subsection. Sufficient conditions will be only pro-
vided through the notion of admissibility.
5.1 Update rule
We can now use the notion of automorphic family
to introduce update rules. An update rule is de-
fined as a family of automorphisms, one for each
extended system A
G
C, with the constraint that
the rule must act reversibly on the set of states
and, by conjugation, on the cone of positive local
transformations.
Definition 32 (Update rule). An update rule
(UR) is a triple (G, A, V
), where V
is an au-
tomorphic family of isometric maps on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
such that
1. the maps
ˆ
V
C
leave [[A
G
C]] invariant, i.e.
ˆ
V
C
[[A
G
C]] = [[A
G
C]]; (65)
2. the map V · V
1
leaves the cones [[A
G
C
A
G
C]]
L+
invariant, i.e. for every A
[[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L+
there are A
0
, A
00
[[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L+
such that
V A V
1
= A
0
, (66)
A = V A
00
V
1
. (67)
The first result is that the inverse of a UR is a
UR.
Lemma 37. Let (G, A, V
) be a UR. Then
(G, A, V
1
) is a UR.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 31
Proof. In the first place, the family V
1
C
is an au-
tomorphic family: items i) and ii) in definition 31
are trivially proved. Now, if kV
C
ak
sup
= kak
sup
for every a [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
QR
, then kV
1
C
ak
sup
=
kV
C
V
1
C
ak
sup
= kak
sup
, which proves isometric-
ity of V
1
C
. From the definition in Eq. (59) one
can easily verify that
ˆ
(V
1
C
) = (
ˆ
V
C
)
1
. Now, it
is a straightforward observation that by Eq. (65),
ˆ
V
1
C
[[A
G
C]] = [[A
G
C]]. Finally, multiplying both
sides of Eq. (66) by V
1
to the left and by V to
the right, for every A [[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L+
one
has
A = V
1
A
0
V ,
which expresses the same condition as in Eq. (67)
for V
1
, and similarly, multiplying both sides of
Eq. (67) by V
1
to the left and by V to the right,
one obtains the same condition as in Eq. (66) for
V
1
.
In the following we will often use V
to de-
note a UR, when G and A
G
are clear from the
context. The symbols
ˆ
V and V
will be often
used instead of
ˆ
V
C
and V
C
, respectively. Accord-
ingly, the symbols a, b, . . . and A , B, . . . will de-
note a e
C
, b e
C
, . . . and A I
C
, B I
C
, . . .,
respectively. Finally, we will sometimes write G
0
for G h
0
with A
h
0
=
C, so that A
G
0
= A
G
C.
The next result states that an update rule
leaves the cone [[A
(Gh
0
)
G
A
(Gh
0
)
G
]]
L+
invariant.
Lemma 38. Let (G, A, V
) be a UR, and define
A
G
0
:
= A
G
C for arbitrary C Sys(Θ). Then the
map V · V
1
leaves the cone [[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
L+
invariant, namely for A [[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
L+
Eqs. (66) and (67) hold with A
0
, A
00
[[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
L+
.
Proof. Let A [[A
G
0
G
A
G
0
G
]]
L+
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
. By definition of UR
V A
G
V
1
= A
0
G
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
.
Moreover, by definition of an automorphic family
of maps and Eq. (64), we have
A
0
[[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
LR
.
The same holds exchanging V
1
and V .
As a consequence of isometricity on [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
QR
,
a UR V
has a dual
ˆ
V that acts isometrically on
[[A
G
C]]
R
.
Lemma 39. Let V
be a UR. The maps
ˆ
V
C
on
[[A
G
0
]]
R
are isometric.
Proof. Let ρ [[A
G
C]]
R
, and remind that
kρk
= sup
kak
sup
=1
|(a|ρ)|.
Then we have
k
ˆ
V
C
ρk
= sup
kak
sup
=1
|(a|
ˆ
V
C
ρ)| = sup
kak
sup
=1
|(V
C
a|ρ)|
= sup
ka
0
k
sup
=1
|(a
0
|ρ)| = kρk
,
thanks to isometricity and invertibility of V
C
.
Corollary 13. Let V
be a UR. Then
ˆ
V
C
[[A
G
C]]
1
= [[A
G
C]]
1
Proof. By eqs. (65) and (29) and isometricity of
ˆ
V
C
, one has
ˆ
V
C
[[A
G
C]]
1
[[A
G
C]]
1
. The same is
true for
ˆ
V
1
C
, thus
ˆ
V
C
[[A
G
C]]
1
= [[A
G
C]]
1
.
The next results will allow us to conclude that
a UR preserves [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
. We start proving that an
update rule V
preserves the unique deterministic
effects e
G
0
.
Lemma 40. If V
is a UR, then V
e
G
0
= e
G
0
,
for A
G
0
:
= A
G
C and arbitrary C Sys(Θ).
Proof. By definition of a UR, for every ρ [[A
G
0
]]
one has
ˆ
V ρ [[A
G
0
]], and lemma 19, gives for
every ρ [[A
G
0
]]
(V
e
G
0
|ρ) = (e
G
0
|
ˆ
V ρ) = k
ˆ
V ρk
= kρk
= (e
G
0
|ρ).
Thanks to theorem 6, we then have V
e
G
0
= e
G
0
.
Corollary 14. Let V
be a UR. Then V
a
h
0
=
a
h
0
for all a
h
0
[[A
(G
0
)
h
0
A
(G
0
)
h
0
]]
QR
.
Proof. By proposition 14, a
h
0
= A
h
0
e
G
0
. Thus,
by definition 31 and lemmas 40 and 56, we have
V
a
h
0
= V
A
h
0
V
1
e
G
0
= A
h
0
e
G
0
= a
h
0
.
We now prove that the cones of effects [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
,
[[
¯
A
G
]]
L+
, [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
and [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
are invariant un-
der the action of any UR.
Lemma 41. Let V
be a UR. Then
V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
= [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
, and V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
=
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
. In particular, for C = I it is
V
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
= [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q+
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 32
Proof. Let a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
. By proposition 14,
there exists A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
such that
a = A
e
G
0
. Then
V
a = V
A
e
G
0
= V
A
V
1
V
e
G
0
= V
A
V
1
e
G
0
= A
0†
e
G
0
= a
0
.
We observe that, by definition of UR and by
lemma 38, V · V
1
preserves the cones [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
. Thus, a
0
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
, and V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
. Since also V
1
is a UR, we have
V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
= [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
. Now, isometricity grants
that Cauchy sequences of local effects in [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
are mapped to Cauchy sequences in [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
L+
,
and that lim
n→∞
V
a
n
= V
lim
n→∞
a
n
. Fi-
nally, by proposition 12, V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
.
Since also V
1
is a UR, we conclude that
V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
= [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
.
Proposition 18. Let V
be a UR. Then
V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
= [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
. In particular, for C = I,
V
[[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
= [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
Proof. Let a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
. Then e
G
0
a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
,
by lemma 12, and thus, by virtue of lemmas 40
and 41, V
a, e
G
0
V
a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q+
. Again by
lemma 12, this implies that V
a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
, and
thus V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
Q
. Finally, since also
V
1
is a UR, the thesis follows.
Let now V
be an update rule. By our def-
inition, the map V · V
1
preserves the cones
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
. We will now prove that V · V
1
also preserves the cones [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
, as well
as the sets of transformations [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L
and
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q
.
We start with the following lemma
Lemma 42. Let V
be a UR. Then V · V
1
leaves the sets [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
invariant, namely
for A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
Eqs. (66) and (67) hold,
with A
0
, A
00
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
. In particular,
for C = I the thesis holds with G
0
= G.
Proof. Let C [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
. By defini-
tion and by lemma 38, V C V
1
= C
0
, and
C = V C
00
V
1
, for C
0
, C
00
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
.
By lemmas 37 and 40,
C
0†
e
G
0
= V
C
V
1
e
G
0
= e
G
0
,
C
00†
e
G
0
= V
1
C
V
e
G
0
= e
G
0
,
and due to lemma 30, C
0
, C
00
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
.
Given a UR V
, the above result allows us to
prove that V ·V
1
maps local transformations to
local transformations, and is isometric on [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
.
Lemma 43. Let V
be a UR, and A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Then V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
, and
kV A V
1
k
sup
= kA k
sup
. (68)
Proof. By proposition 16, there exists C
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
such that
kA k
sup
C ± A 0.
By definition of a UR, we then have
kA k
sup
V C V
1
± V A V
1
0, (69)
and being V C V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
, it follows that V A V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Consequently, we have
V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
.
Finally, since V
1
is a UR, we have that
V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
.
Moreover, by lemma 42, Eq. (69) implies that
kA k
sup
J(V A V
1
). Thus kV A V
1
k
sup
kA k
sup
. Now, being V
1
a UR, the equality
kV A V
1
k
sup
= kA k
sup
follows.
Lemma 44. Let V
be a UR. Then V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
, and
lim
n→∞
V A
n
V
1
= V ( lim
n→∞
A
n
)V
1
. (70)
Proof. Since V · V
1
is isometric and surjective
on the dense submanifolds [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
, by
lemma 43 it maps Cauchy sequences to Cauchy
sequences, and their equivalence classes to equiv-
alence classes, thus it maps [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
QR
to itself. Surjectivity follows from surjectivity
on [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Eq. (70) can be indepen-
dently checked applying both sides to arbitrary
a [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
QR
.
Lemma 45. Let V
be a UR. Then V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q1
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q1
.
Proof. Let {C
n
}
nN
be a Cauchy sequence in
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
. Then by definition of UR
and lemma 44 we have that {V C
n
V
1
}
nN
is a
Cauchy sequence in [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L1
, and its limit
V C V
1
is in [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q1
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 33
The last results finally allow us to prove that
for a UR V
, the map V ·V
1
preserves the cones
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
.
Lemma 46. Let V
be a UR. Then V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
.
Proof. By lemmas 38 and 44, along with the defi-
nition of a UR, V ·V
1
maps Cauchy sequences in
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
to Cauchy sequences in [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L+
, thus V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
. Since V
1
is a UR, the thesis fol-
lows.
Next, we show that for a UR V
, V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
LR
=
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
LR
.
Lemma 47. Let V
be a UR. Then
V
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
LR
= [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
LR
.
Proof. Let a
R
[[
¯
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Then by proposi-
tion 14
a
R
= A
R
e
G
0
,
for some A
R
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Now, we have
V
a
R
= V
A
R
e
G
0
= V
A
R
V
1
e
G
0
,
and by lemma 43 V
A
R
V
1
= A
0†
R
0
with A
0
R
0
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
LR
. Then V
a
R
= a
0
R
0
, with R
0
R
(G
0
)
. As to surjectivity, it can be straightfor-
wardly proved exploiting lemma 37.
Finally, for a UR V
, the map V ·V
1
preserves
the set of quasi-local transformations.
Lemma 48. Let V
be a UR. Then one has
V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q
, (71)
V [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L
V
1
= [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L
. (72)
Proof. Let A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q
. Then kA k
sup
1, and by proposition 17, there is C [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q1
such that
C A 0.
By lemma 46, V A V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q+
.
Moreover, by lemma 42,V C V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q1
. By the above observations, we have
V A V
1
0,
V C V
1
V A V
1
0.
Finally, by lemma 32, one has
V A V
1
, V C V
1
V A V
1
[[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
Q
.
The same argument holds for A [[A
G
0
A
G
0
]]
L
. Since V
1
is a UR, surjectivity on both
sets is proved.
Clearly, given a UR V
, the image of the alge-
bra of local transformations of A
g
under V · V
1
,
i.e.
V [[A
(G
0
)
g
A
(G
0
)
g
]]
QR
V
1
[[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
QR
,
is a subalgebra of [[A
(G
0
)
G
A
(G
0
)
G
]]
QR
isomorphic
to [[A
(G
0
)
g
A
(G
0
)
g
]]
QR
.
5.2 Admissibility and local action
As we have seen, independently of the nature of
system C, the map V · V
1
does more than map-
ping linear maps to linear maps: it sends transfor-
mations to transformations. This is an important
result, as the definitions of automorphic family
and UR are meant to embody necessary condi-
tions for a family of maps to represent V I
C
.
However, URs are not yet consistent with such
a factorisation. The reason for this is that lo-
cal discriminability in our theory is not assumed.
Thus, while knowledge of the linear maps V
C
is
sufficient to determine the action of the UR on
factorised effects a
G
b
C
and, by conjugation, on
generalised transformations A
G
I
C
, and such
actions are consistent with a factorised action of
the form V I
C
, still we do not have enough in-
formation to determine the action of V
C
on those
elements of [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
QR
that lie outside the sub-
space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
[[
¯
C]]
QR
(and analogously for the
conjugate action on transformations). For this
purpose we introduce in this section the notion
of admissibility.
We remind that G
0
stands for G h
0
, with
A
h
0
=
C for some system C. Let R R
(G
0
)
be
a finite region. Since [[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
is isomorphic to
[[
¯
A
R
]]
R
, whose size is D
R
:
= D
A
R
, we can find a
basis {b
jR
}
D
R
j=1
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
. Thus, by lemma 47,
V
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
0
]]
QR
for some finite region
R
0
R
(G
0
)
, that can be obtained as
R
0
:
=
D
R
[
j=1
R
0
j
, V
b
jR
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
0
j
]]
QR
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 34
This implies that, for every finite region R
R
(G
0
)
, the UR V
induces a linear map V (R)
:
[[
¯
A
R
]]
R
[[
¯
A
R
0
]]
R
. The following definition of ad-
missible UR is now given in terms of the proper-
ties of the induced maps V (R)
.
Definition 33. Let (G, A, V
) be a UR, and
let V (R)
be the induced maps on finite regions
R G
0
, for arbitrary choice of A
h
0
=
C. We call
the UR admissible if for every finite S R
(G)
the
family of maps V (S h
0
)
represents a transfor-
mation V
S
[[A
S
0
A
S
]]
R
, i.e.
V (S h
0
)
= V
S
I
C
. (73)
Consider now a partition G = R
¯
R, where
¯
R
:
= G \ R. We will write A
G
= A
R
A
¯
R
.
By definition, the space [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
of quasi-local ef-
fects contains the spaces [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
and [[
¯
A
(G)
¯
R
]]
QR
as closed subspaces. However, if the theory does
not satisfy local discriminability, it is not true
in general that [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
= [[
¯
A
(G)
R
]]
QR
[[
¯
A
(G)
¯
R
]]
QR
.
This makes it difficult to define a UR of the form
V W .
In the remainder of the section we close this
gap. For this purpose, we start defining what it
means, for a UR V
on A
G
, to act locally on R
in symbols V
= V
0†
I
¯
R
. For our purpose,
we then need to provide a suitable definition of
the identity V
= V
0†
I
¯
R
, which satisfies the
necessary (but not sufficient) condition
(V
0†
I
¯
R
)(a
S
b
T
) = (V
0†
a
S
) (b
T
),
for every S, T R
(G)
such that S R and T
¯
R.
Definition 34. Let V
be a UR for A
G
. We
say that V
acts locally on the region R G
if for every C and every finite region S R
(G
0
)
with G
0
= G h
0
and A
h
0
=
C, the induced map
V (S)
has the form
V
(S) = W
SR
I
S\R
. (74)
As a consequence of the above definition we
now prove the following result, for which we do
not provide the proof, that is straightforward.
Lemma 49. Let (G, A, V
) be a UR acting lo-
cally on R. Then
V
(a
S
b
T
) = (W
S
a
S
) b
T
, (75)
for S R and T
¯
R. In particular,
V
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
= [[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
, and V
b = b for every
b [[
¯
A
(G
0
)
¯
R
]]
QR
.
Lemma 50. Let (G, A, V
) be a UR act-
ing locally on R. Then there exists a UR
(R, A, V
0†
) such that V
J
1
R
0
a = J
1
R
0
V
0†
a
and V
1
J
1
R
0
a = J
1
R
0
V
0−1
a for every a
[[
¯
A
R
0
]]
QR
, with A
R
0
:
= A
R
C.
Proof. Linearity and isometricity of the restric-
tion V
R
0
of V
to [[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
0
]]
QR
are straightforward
by lemma 49. Thus, also V
0†
:
= J
R
0
V
R
0
J
1
R
0
is linear and isometric. Let now A [[A
R
0
A
R
0
]]
Q
. Then one has
V
0†
A
V
0−1
= J
R
0
V
R
0
J
1
R
0
A
J
R
0
V
1
R
0
J
1
R
0
= J
R
0
V
R
0
A
R
0
V
1
R
0
J
1
R
0
= J
R
0
(V
A
R
0
V
1
)
R
0
J
1
R
0
,
where A
R
0
:
= J
1
R
0
A
J
R
0
. In the above chain
of equalities we used the fact that, since V
,
V
1
and A
R
0
preserve the space [[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
0
]]
QR
, then
also V
A
R
0
V
1
does, and one can thus define
its restriction (V
A
R
0
V
1
)
R
0
. Finally, since
V
is a UR, one has V
A
R
0
V
1
= A
0†
with
A
0
[[A
(G
0
)
R
0
A
(G
0
)
R
0
]]
Q
. Thus, V
0−1
A V
0
[[A
R
0
A
R
0
]]
Q
. A similar argument leads to
the existence of A
00
[[A
R
0
A
R
0
]]
Q
such that
A = V
0−1
A
00
V
0
. Now, let ρ [[A
G
]]. Then ρ
defines a state ρ
|R
0
on [[
¯
A
R
0
]]
QR
, by lemma 17,
with
(a|ρ
|R
0
) = (a
R
0
|ρ) = (J
1
R
0
a|ρ),
for every a
R
0
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
0
]]
QR
. Now, we have
(a|[
ˆ
V ρ]
|R
0
) = (J
1
R
0
a|
ˆ
V ρ) = (V
J
1
R
0
a|ρ)
= (V
R
0
J
1
R
0
a|ρ) = (J
1
R
0
J
R
0
V
R
0
J
1
R
0
a|ρ)
= (J
1
R
0
V
0†
a|ρ) = (a|
ˆ
V
0
ρ
|R
0
).
We then showed that [
ˆ
V ρ]
|R
0
=
ˆ
V
0
(ρ
|R
0
). More-
over, since V preserves the set of states, [
ˆ
V ρ]
|R
0
is a state. Thus,
ˆ
V
0
[[A
R
0
]] [[A
R
0
]]. The same
argument for V
0−1
brings to the conclusion that
ˆ
V
0
[[A
R
0
]] = [[A
R
0
]]. Thus, V
0†
is a UR for A
R
.
Moreover
V
J
1
R
0
a = V
R
0
J
1
R
0
a = J
1
R
0
V
0†
a,
and the same holds for V
1
.
In the following, under the hypothesis of
lemma 50, we will write V
= V
0†
I
¯
R
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 35
Lemma 51. Let V
be a UR for [[
¯
A
G
]]
R
that acts
locally on R, and W
a UR that acts locally on
¯
R. Then V
0†
W
0†
:
= V
W
= W
V
.
We can now define a global update rule as fol-
lows.
Definition 35 (Global update rule). Let
(G, A, V
) be a UR. We call (G, A, V
) a Global
Update Rule (GUR), or global rule for short, if
(G, A, V
) and (G, A, V
1
) are admissible.
Remark 6. The set of GURs (G, A, V
) is a
group. The proof of closure under composi-
tion and associativity are tedious but straightfor-
ward, and we omit them here. Moreover, given
(G, A, V
) and (F, A, W
) one can define their
parallel composition as (G F, A, V
W
).
The analysis of properties of parallel composition
is beyond the scope of the present work, and will
be the subject of further studies.
We now provide an important example of
GUR. Let G = H ×{0, 1}, and let H
i
:
= (H, i) for
i = 0, 1. Let a
R
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
with A
h
0
=
C. Let
R G = (R
0
, 0) (R
1
, 1). Then we define
˜
R
:
=
R
0
R
1
H, and
¯
R
:
=
˜
R × {0, 1} R. Clearly,
R
¯
R. If (h, i)
¯
R, then also (h, i1)
¯
R. Let
then ¯a
¯
R
:
= a
R
e
¯
R\R
.
Now, for every T
R
(H)
let us define the GUR
(G, A, S
T
) by setting
S
T
[a
R
]
:
=
h
S
˜
RT
¯a
¯
R
i
, (76)
where S
X
:
=
N
hX
S
h
for X R
(H)
, and S
h
is the map that swaps A
(h,0)
and A
(h,1)
. It is
straightforward to verify that, for every T R
(H)
,
S
T
is a UR. Being defined in terms of induced
maps, it is immediate to verify that S
T
admissi-
ble. Moreover, S
T
is involutive, i.e. S
1
T
= S
T
.
Of particular interest for the following is the GUR
(G, A, S
H
).
Notice that, for a finite disjoint partition H =
k
i=1
S
k
, we have S
H
=
N
k
i=1
S
S
k
. Thus, by
lemma 51, for every GUR (G, A, V
), and for ev-
ery i, j, we have
V (S
S
i
S
j
I
H\(S
i
S
j
)
)V
1
= V (S
S
i
I
H\S
i
)V
1
V (S
S
j
I
H\S
j
)V
1
= V (S
S
j
I
H\S
j
)V
1
V (S
S
i
I
H\S
i
)V
1
,
where I
S
denotes I
(S,0)
I
(S,1)
.
For A [[A
R
A
R
]], it is easily verified that
A
(R,1)
= S
H
(A
(R,0)
)S
H
= S
R
(A I
R
)S
R
,
A
(R,0)
= S
H
(A
(R,1)
)S
H
= S
R
(I
R
A )S
R
.
(77)
Finally, let us consider a GUR (G, A, U
V
).
One can prove that S
H
(U V )S
H
= V U ,
by the following argument. Let us consider a
[[
¯
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
QR
. Then
S
H
(U V )
S
H
a
R
= S
H
(U V )
(S
˜
R
a)
¯
R
= S
H
[(U (
˜
R, 0)
V (
˜
R, 1)
)(S
˜
R
a)]
¯
R
= [S
˜
R
(U (
˜
R, 0)
V (
˜
R, 1)
)(S
˜
R
a)]
¯
R
= [V (
˜
R, 0)
U (
˜
R, 1)
a]
¯
R
= (V U )
a
R
.
5.3 Causal influence
In the present subsection we define the notion of
causal influence that establishes, given a GUR,
whether the evolution allows interventions on one
system to affect other systems after one step, or
more generally how many steps are needed for
such an influence to occur. We will often use the
notation [[A
(G)
R
C A
(G)
R
C]]
∗∗
to denote [[A
(G
0
)
R
A
(G
0
)
R
]]
∗∗
, with G
0
= G h
0
and A
h
0
=
C. In the
following we also adopt the convention that for
R R
(G)
,
¯
R denotes the complementary region
¯
R
:
= G \ R. Notice that, consistently with the
notation R = g, we will write ¯g to denote G \ g.
Definition 36 (Causal influence). We say that,
according to the global rule V , system g does not
causally influence g
0
if for every external system
C
V [[A
(G)
g
C A
(G)
g
C]]
QR
V
1
[[A
(G)
¯g
0
C A
(G)
¯g
0
C]]
QR
.
On the other hand, we will say that according
to the global rule V system g causally influences
system g
0
, and write g g
0
, in the opposite case,
i.e. when
C, F [[A
(G)
g
C A
(G)
g
C]]
QR
:
(V I
C
)F (V
1
I
C
) 6∈ [[A
(G)
¯g
0
C A
(G)
¯g
0
C]]
QR
.
The above definition gets a clear meaning as a
diagram: according to V there is causal influence
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 36
from g to g
0
if there exists F [[A
g
C A
g
C]]
such that
C
F
C
g
V
1
V
g
¯g ¯g
6=
C
F
0
C
¯g
0
¯g
0
g
0
g
0
,
(78)
and even better in the form
C
F
C
g
V
g
¯g ¯g
6=
C
F
0
C
¯g
0
V
¯g
0
g
0
g
0
.
Definition 37. We define forward and backward
g-neighbourhoods the sets N
+
g
:
= {g
0
|g g
0
}
and N
g
:
= {g
0
|g
0
g}, respectively.
In terms of diagrams, the forward g-
neighbourhood A
N
+
g
of g can be understood as
the smallest region K =
N
kK
A
g
0
k
such that for
every k K there exists C and F [[A
(G)
g
C
A
(G)
g
C]]
QR
such that
C
F
C
g
V
g
¯g ¯g
(79)
=
C
F
0
C
N
+
g
V
N
+
g
¯
N
+
g
¯
N
+
g
.
with F
0
acting non trivially on g
0
k
, namely F
0
6∈
[[A
(G)
¯g
0
k
C A
(G)
¯g
0
k
C]]
QR
. Notice that g may or may
not belong to N
+
g
.
Analogously to the definition of N
±
g
, one can
give a definition of N
±
R
for every finite region R
G.
Definition 38. We say that the system g
0
belongs
to the forward neighbourhood of R, and write g
0
N
+
R
, if
C, F [[A
(G)
R
C A
(G)
R
C]]
QR
:
(V I
C
)F (V
1
I
C
) 6∈ [[A
(G)
¯g
0
C A
(G)
¯g
0
C]]
QR
.
The backward neighbourhood N
R
of R is defined
as
N
R
:
= {g
0
G | N
+
g
0
R 6= ∅}. (80)
Clearly, one has
N
+
R
[
gR
N
+
g
. (81)
We will prove that the latter is actually an equal-
ity in the next section.
One might define causal influence without in-
voking any external system C, as follows.
Definition 39 (Individual influence). We say
that the system g does not individually influence
g
0
if
V [[A
(G)
g
A
(G)
g
]]
QR
V
1
[[A
(G)
¯g
0
A
(G)
¯g
0
]]
QR
.
On the other hand, we will say that according to
the global rule V system g individually influences
system g
0
, and write g
g
g
0
, in the opposite
case, i.e. when
F [A
(G)
g
A
(G)
g
]
QR
:
V F V
1
6∈ [[A
(G)
¯g
0
A
(G)
¯g
0
]]
QR
.
The individual forward neighbourhood of g is
N
+
g
(g)
:
= {g
0
G | g
g
g
0
}.
A second definition that can be given without
referring to external systems C is the following.
Definition 40 (Cooperative influence). We say
that the region S does not cooperatively influence
g
0
if
V [[A
(G)
S
A
(G)
S
]]
QR
V
1
[[A
(G)
¯g
0
A
(G)
¯g
0
]]
QR
.
In the opposite case we will write S
S
g
0
. The
cooperative forward neighbourhood of a region S
is defined as
N
+
S
(S)
:
= {g
0
G | S
S
g
0
}.
Notice now that in a theory without local dis-
criminability it may happen that a system g does
not individually influence g
0
but it does cooper-
atively, namely one can have g
0
N
+
S
(S), but
g
0
6∈ N
+
g
(g) for any g S. In other words,
N
+
S
(S)
S
hS
N
+
h
(h). We call this phenomenon
non-local activation of causal influence. If such
a phenomenon occurs, however, it can be hard
to establish which of the “cooperating” systems
h S is responsible for causal influence on
g
0
N
+
S
(S). This is the reason why we prefer
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 37
the former definition of causal influence, which
provides also this piece of information.
Given a GUR (G, A, V
), we can now construct
a graph Γ(G, E) with vertices g G and edges
E
:
= {(g, g
0
) G × G|g g
0
}. We call such a
graph the graph of causal influence of the GUR
V
. In the next section we will prove that, if we
denote by N
±∗
g
the neighbourhoods for the GUR
V
1
, the following relations hold
N
±
f
= N
∓∗
f
. (82)
We also define the local perspective present P
+
R
of R R
(G)
as the set P
+
R
:
= N
N
+
R
R,
namely the set of systems that can causally in-
fluence the one-step future N
+
R
of R. Similarly
one can define the local retrospective present of R
as P
R
:
= N
+
N
R
R, namely the set of systems
that can be influenced by the one-step past N
R
of R. In general, P
+
R
6= P
R
. We will also need to
refer to the sets P
+
R
:
= N
+
N
+
R
.
5.3.1 Relation with signalling
The term influence that we used above is pre-
cisely defined in Eq. (78). In the present sub-
section we will make a clear point that this def-
inition is stronger than the notion of signalling
that is customary in the literature on quantum
information theory [52, 53, 54] or in general op-
erational probabilistic theories [15]. In that con-
text, a channel C [[AB A
0
B
0
]] is called non-
signalling (or semicausal) from B to A
0
if there
exists F [[A A
0
]] such that
A
C
A
0
B B
0
e
=
A
F
A
0
B
e
. (83)
We will now show that, under the hypothesis that
N
+
g
is finite for every g G, the condition of
Eq. 79, in a suitably defined sense, implies that
of Eq. (83). Let us consider the state ρ [[A
G
]]
R
.
Then (a
S
|
ˆ
A
T
ρ)
:
= (a
0
ST
|ρ) = (A
T
a
S
|ρ). In the
case where a
S
= e
G
, (A
T
e
G
|ρ) = (b
T
|ρ), where
b = A
e
T
. Let us now consider (
ˆ
V ρ)
|R
, which
by definition is the state in [[A
R
]]
R
such that, for
every a [[
¯
A
R
]]
R
(a|[
ˆ
V ρ]
|R
) = (J
R
a|
ˆ
V ρ) = (a
R
|
ˆ
V ρ).
Now, by lemma 31, one has
(a
R
|
ˆ
V ρ) = (e
G
|
ˆ
A
R
ˆ
V ρ)
= (e
G
|
ˆ
V
ˆ
V
1
ˆ
A
R
ˆ
V ρ)
= (e
G
|
ˆ
V
ˆ
A
0
N
+
R
ρ)
= (e
G
|
ˆ
A
0
N
+
R
ρ)
= (b
N
+
R
|ρ) = (b|ρ
|N
+
R
).
In order to determine [
ˆ
V ρ]
|R
it is sufficient to
know ρ
|N
+
R
. Indeed, the linear map V
R
:
[[A
N
+
R
]]
R
[[A
R
]]
R
gives
(
ˆ
V ρ)
|R
= V
R
(ρ
|N
+
R
). (84)
Diagrammatically, the equality can be recast,
with a slight abuse of notation, as in Eq. 83, as
follows
N
+
R
V
R
N
+
R
¯
R
e
=
N
+
R
V
R
R
N
+
R
e
.
Notice that, by the no-restriction hypothesis, for
an admissible V the map V
R
is linear and admis-
sible, and is thus a transformation in [[A
(G)
N
+
R
A
(G)
R
]]. Moreover,
V
a
R
= (V
R
a)
N
+
R
. (85)
Finally, notice that by definition V
R
e
R
= e
N
+
R
,
namely V
R
[[A
(G)
N
+
R
A
(G)
R
]]
1
. The argument
can be repeated for the case where N
+
g
is not
finite, as long as N
+
g
G.
We remark that in the case of Quantum or
Fermionic cellular automata, the condition for
no causal influence is equivalent to no-signalling,
while in the case of Classical cellular automata
no causal influence is strictly stronger than no-
signalling. In a different context, a difference be-
tween the two notions was pointed out in Ref. [55]
5.4 Block decomposition
Let us now consider the GUR (G, A, W
) where
we set G = H × {0, 1}, and W = V
H
0
V
1
H
1
,
for an arbitrary GUR (H, A, V
), H
i
denoting a
shorthand for (H, i). We observe that
W = V
H
0
V
1
H
1
= (V
H
0
I
H
1
)S
H
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)S
H
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 38
Then, by Eq. (76), given R A
G
and a
[[
¯
A
(G)
R
¯
C]]
QR
, with R G = (R
0
, 0) (R
1
, 1),
W
a
RC
= (W
a)
R
0
C
=[S
H
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
S
H
(V
H
0
I
H
1
)
]a
RC
=[S
H
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
S
H
]a
0
R
00
C
=[S
H
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
S
N
+
R
0
R
1
]a
0
R
00
C
=[S
H
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
S
N
+
R
0
R
1
(V
H
0
I
H
1
)
]a
RC
,
where a
0
:
= (V
H
0
I
H
1
)
a, R
0
:
=
(N
+
R
0
, 0) (N
+
R
1
, 1), and R
00
:
= (N
+
R
0
, 0)(R
1
, 1).
Now, defining for S R
(H)
S
0
S
:
=
Y
hS
S
0
h
, (86)
S
0
h
:
= (V
H
0
I
H
1
)S
h
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
), (87)
thanks to eq. (77) we have
(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
S
N
+
R
0
R
1
(V
H
0
I
H
1
)
= S
0†
N
+
R
0
R
1
.
We remark that, since (V
H
0
I
H
1
)·(V
1
H
0
I
H
1
)
is an automorphism of [[A
G
A
G
]]
QR
, one has
S
0
f
S
0
g
= S
0
g
S
0
f
, f, g H. (88)
Thus, the product
Q
hN
+
R
S
0
h
in Eq. (86) is well
defined. Notice also that, by definition
S
0
h
S
0
h
= I
G
. (89)
Since S
0
h
[[A
(G)
(N
+
h
,0)(h,1)
A
(G)
(N
+
h
,0)(h,1)
]]
Q1
(see Fig. 1), one has that S
0
N
+
R
0
R
1
[[A
(G)
S
A
(G)
S
]]
Q1
, with
S
:
= (N
+
N
+
R
0
N
+
R
1
, 0) (N
+
R
0
R
1
, 1).
Then we can write
W
a
RC
= S
H
S
0†
N
+
R
0
R
1
a
RC
= S
N
+
N
+
R
0
N
+
R
1
N
+
R
0
R
1
S
0†
N
+
R
0
R
1
a
RC
.
However, due to the structure of W
, one actually
has
(S
0
N
+
R
0
R
1
I
C
)
a
RC
= a
00
(N
+
R
1
,0)(N
+
R
0
,1)C
,
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
N
+
g
<latexit sha1_base64="BwrvXqGnggqGLKZdAjge0VPBxDQ=">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</latexit>
N
+
g
<latexit sha1_base64="BwrvXqGnggqGLKZdAjge0VPBxDQ=">AAAIVHicdZVbb9s2FMfVdl28bOva7XEv7NQC3RYEljdsewiCxo5zadrU18RJlQUURTmCqEtIuojB6kvsdftcA/Zd9jBKJMW66QQY1vmd/7nwSKSCgsSMt9v/3Ll775P7n661Plv//IsvH3z18NHXJyxfUISnKCc5nQWQYRJneMpjTvCsoBimAcGnQdKr/KdvMWVxnk34ssAXKZxncRQjyCWaHf8ufvyhvJxfPnTbm+36ArdvPH3jOvoaXD5a+8UPc7RIccYRgYy98doFvxCQ8hgRXK77C4YLiBI4x6JuswRPJQpBlFP5yzio6YoOpiyF/GpD/rNlGmwwnkK6pOFGkMroysVW9BWhLGLlx7J8LOLNgke/XYg4KxYcZ0i1FC0I4DmopgPCmGLEyVLeQERjuRaAriCFiMsZrlSZU1hcxeimXH+60tIyxHVDdQ1wswT+zTIvqmELSIhxSN0QxRQtYi6RDPFZgVxPCL/uOQKuVxrHgaic4EDbA5rnkdThkCVx4ReQ+lkeZ6F8EMIPIlD7N4EJv8aheOJv+AGRHbLrBaT4SRVUAuXvpQW5UWWDAPR01LbwKczm9YOs7C3hE2XXZpIIf9t/DPxtZQeB8Lf8x/5WCWqb04xFNJULUutBtFpQ7SLZB06aVj4VR3fkBCTYKZWYdpXdNauhPQV6RrCr7N3SrIf2FemXJueeAntWsq/IfiM5VOCwKYMUQKbMUNlDm2OkyKjJMVZgbCUzRWaN5EyBMys5V+S8IXxHmOnJKSjUtairG+Q9y3patmvRbpNubOFY6/Yt2jfpXlr2UsuOLTo2siPLjsyjPrTs0Ogmlk10uqlF06a7EwtPtO7UolOT7pVlr7RsZtHMyM4sO9Oyc4vOjWzPMvlSKPbastdG17esbxb74r3YF0Y4snCk8w0sGoDy/5/FyqDMjsw4w7w5CkQ/isrm/Riv+sbcuiYy0fu+idzBrArV5Ye21lCzOS3qQyfISViduDkR1cGjVzsuYGYrScOkSriMeud6cvsDJQ1otZ23XO+dloSJliSJ0YRBpQkCKzpSmu+NoivtZ9Y97rme26mJ22lEE6r2zIQ2JySCtbCu73ZsV7elfQ4rIg70xpYDqwewcuKOMCRMNGfiyPDgLVZndBCpMWksh1S5QGZAokFiwLUG1+W6/NJ6H35Xb9+cdDa9nzY7w5/d5139zW053zrfOc8cz/nVee4cOANn6iCHOH84fzp/rf299m/rXuu+kt69o2O+cVau1oP/ACwd7HE=</latexit>
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
N
+
gg
0
<latexit sha1_base64="wz3Ic4ddhaPK7hsdsCPvkZUHq0E=">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</latexit>
N
+
gg
0
<latexit sha1_base64="wz3Ic4ddhaPK7hsdsCPvkZUHq0E=">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</latexit>
g
0
<latexit sha1_base64="OdrFQMI7pWiSOv9qWZomaKsMoVI=">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</latexit>
g
0
<latexit sha1_base64="OdrFQMI7pWiSOv9qWZomaKsMoVI=">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</latexit>
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
g
<latexit sha1_base64="fS8RMo7GVe9yoxqmeAyPzqMQOd4=">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</latexit>
N
+
gg
0
<latexit sha1_base64="wz3Ic4ddhaPK7hsdsCPvkZUHq0E=">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</latexit>
N
+
gg
0
<latexit sha1_base64="wz3Ic4ddhaPK7hsdsCPvkZUHq0E=">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</latexit>
g
0
<latexit sha1_base64="OdrFQMI7pWiSOv9qWZomaKsMoVI=">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</latexit>
g
0
<latexit sha1_base64="OdrFQMI7pWiSOv9qWZomaKsMoVI=">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</latexit>
Figure 1: In the top picture we provide a graphical rep-
resentation of the transformation S
0
g
, with input wires
on the top left and output on the bottom right. In the
bottom picture we provide a graphical illustration of the
identity S
0
g
S
0
g
0
= S
0
g
0
S
0
g
.
and finally this implies that
W
a
RC
= (S
N
+
R
0
N
+
R
1
S
0†
N
+
R
0
R
1
I
C
)a
RC
.
(90)
We now observe that
W
1
= V
1
H
0
V
H
1
= S
H
W S
H
,
and thus, by Eq. (90), it is
W
1
a
RC
= (S
0
N
+
R
1
R
0
I
C
)
a
0
R
0
C
= (S
0†
N
+
R
1
R
0
S
R
0
R
1
I
C
)a
RC
, (91)
where a
0
R
0
C
= [S
a]
(R
1
,0)(R
0
,1)C
. Let us then
consider R
1
= . In this case for [a
(R,0)C
]
[[
¯
A
(G)
(R,0)
¯
C]], being R = (R, 0) (, 1), it holds that
[(V
a)
(N
+
R
,0)C
] = S
N
+
R
S
0†
N
+
R
I
C
[a
(R,0)C
],
(92)
[(V
1
a)
(N
+
R
,0)C
] = S
0†
R
S
R
I
C
[a
(R,0)C
]. (93)
In view of the above results, we now consider the
maps V A V
1
for A [[A
(R,0)
C A
(R,0)
C]]
R
,
with R R
(H)
. First of all, we observe that
(V A V
1
) I
H
1
= W (A I
H
1
)W
1
is a local transformation in [[A
(G)
(N
+
R
,0)
C
A
(G)
(N
+
R
,0)
C]]
QR
. Let then a [[
¯
A
(G)
˜
S
¯
C]]
R
for S
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 39
R
(H)
. We have the following (see Appendix C)
[(V A V
1
) I
H
1
]
a
˜
SC
=[W (A I
H
1
)W
1
]
a
˜
SC
=(S
0†
R
S
R
I
C
)(A I
H
0
)
(S
R
S
0†
R
I
C
)a
˜
SC
.
Finally, since this holds for every a, we have that
for A [[A
(R,0)
C A
(R,0)
C]]
R
(V A V
1
) I
H
1
=(S
0
R
I
C
)(I
H
0
A )(S
0
R
I
C
). (94)
The above relation, considering Eq. (86), shows
that
N
+
R
[
gR
N
+
g
.
Along with Eq. (81) the latter proves that actu-
ally
N
+
R
=
[
gR
N
+
g
. (95)
Analogously, since N
R
= {g
0
| g R, g N
+
g
0
},
it is
N
R
= {g
0
| g R, g
0
N
g
} =
[
gR
N
g
. (96)
Let us finally consider the maps (V
1
BV ) for
B [[A
(R,1)
C A
(R,1)
C]]
R
, with R R
(H)
.
In this case, using Eq. (89) and manipulating
Eq. (94) we obtain
I
H
0
(V
1
BV )
= (S
0
N
+
R
I
C
)(B I
H
1
)(S
0
N
+
R
I
C
).
(97)
Since the S
0
h
’s that do not commute with B
I
H
1
in Eq. (97) correspond to h N
g
for some
g R, namely h N
R
, we can conclude that
N
+
R
N
R
. (98)
This observation is sufficient to prove that N
±∗
R
=
N
R
, as anticipated in the previous section.
Lemma 52. Let (G, A, V
) be a GUR. Then
N
±∗
R
= N
R
. (99)
Proof. We remind that g N
±
f
iff f N
g
. Now,
considering Eq. (98) for R = g we have that
g
0
N
−∗
g
g N
+
g
0
g N
g
0
g
0
N
+
g
.
This implies that N
−∗
g
N
+
g
. Exchanging V
and V
1
, we can conclude that N
+
g
N
g
N
+
g
, i.e. N
+
g
= N
g
. The thesis follows invoking
Eqs. (95) and (96), which then give us
N
R
= N
+
R
.
In the remainder we will then use N
±
R
and P
±
R
,
and abandon the symbols N
±∗
R
and P
±∗
R
.
We observe that the block decomposition of
V V
1
that we achieved through the block
transformations S
0
g
is a generalisation of a result
that was proved for quantum cellular automata
in Ref. [32]. Local rules of other kinds are used
in the literature, with nice properties that the
present block decomposition lacks, such as com-
posability (see e.g. Ref [56]). However, for later
purposes the block form of Eq. (86) is particularly
suitable in our case, to cope with update rules in
theories without local discriminability.
6 Homogeneity
The principle of homogeneity, as it is usually for-
mulated in physics, regards equivalence of points
in space-time. Here, however, space-time is not
the background for occurrence of physical events,
on the contrary it emerges as a convenient de-
scription of relations between information pro-
cessing events. We then provide a definition
of homogeneity for a global update rule, that
regards the way in which different systems are
treated by the evolution. In particular, roughly
speaking, every system must be treated in the
same way by the GUR.
It would be easy to state the homogeneity prin-
ciple if we knew in advance that the set G has
some geometric structure that is invariant under
the action of a group—technically speaking, if G
were a symmetric space—so that we could de-
fine pairs of homologous regions as those mapped
into one another by some group element. In this
case, we could provide a criterion for the evolu-
tion to treat every system in the same way, con-
sisting in the existence of some representation of
the group of symmetries of the set G that con-
nects the evolution of every two homologous re-
gions. The group in this case would provide the
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 40
two following ingredients that are needed for the
definition of homogeneity: i) a notion of “running
the same test on different regions”, and ii) a cri-
terion for equivalence of two homologous regions
provided by the requirement that the events of
the same test in the two regions have equal prob-
abilities, if the regions are prepared in the same
state.
However, we are in a situation where the struc-
ture of G must emerge from the evolution given
by the global rule V . The detailed idea is thus to
turn the above argument on its head, and define
two regions to be homologous if they are “treated
in the same way" by V . The precise construction
is the following.
First of all, in order for the dynamics to treat
two regions in the same way, the two regions need
to have the same structure, in such a way that we
can make sense of “performing the same range of
tests in the two different regions”. This concept is
captured by the extension of the notion of oper-
ational equivalence (see definition 2) to regions.
Intuitively, two operationally equivalent regions
must correspond to operationally equivalent sys-
tems. However, they also need to“have the same
structure”, where the term structure refers to the
fact that a system A
R
associated with a region
R is decomposed in a preferred way into subsys-
tems A
g
i
corresponding to the cells that compose
the region R = {g
1
, g
2
, . . . , g
k
}. The notion of
operational equivalence of regions must then also
capture the idea that two equivalent regions ad-
mit equivalent decompositions.
The definition is thus recursive, starting from
elementary regions R = {g}, and then defining
equivalence of R
1
and R
2
as the equivalence of
any strict subregion S
1
R
1
with a strict subre-
gion S
2
R
2
, and viceversa.
We recall Remark 5, namely that for the re-
mainder every elementary region g G corre-
sponds to some non-trivial system, A
g
6' I.
Definition 41. Two elementary regions g and h
are operationally equivalent if A
g
=
A
h
. Two fi-
nite regions R
1
, R
2
G are operationally equiv-
alent if A
R
1
' A
R
2
, and for every S
1
R
1
there
exists S
2
R
2
, and viceversa for every S
2
R
2
there exists S
1
R
1
, such that A
S
1
and A
S
2
are
operationally equivalent.
Two operationally equivalent regions have the
same structure, namely they can be decomposed
into pairwise equivalent subsystems, as we now
prove.
Lemma 53. An elementary region R
1
= {g}
cannot be operationally equivalent to a non-
elementary one R
2
= {h
1
, . . . , h
k
}.
Proof. The statement is trivial, since R
1
= {g
1
}
does not have proper subregions, while any non-
elementary region R
2
does, so operational equiv-
alence cannot hold.
Lemma 54. The regions R
1
and R
2
are op-
erationally equivalent if and only if R
1
=
{g
1
, g
2
, . . . , g
k
}, R
2
= {h
1
, h
2
, . . . h
k
}, and A
g
i
=
A
h
i
.
Proof. The condition is clearly sufficient, as one
can immediately realise by considering the re-
versible transformation T
S
[[A
S
1
A
S
2
]]
1
de-
fined as T
S
:
=
N
g
j
S
1
T
j
, with T
j
[[A
g
j
A
h
j
]]
1
reversible for every j = 1, . . . , k. We now
prove that the condition is necessary. Let R
1
and R
2
be operationally equivalent. By defini-
tion, and by lemma 53, for every g
l
R
1
there
is h
m
R
2
such that A
g
l
=
A
h
m
, and viceversa.
We now introduce the equivalence relation
g
i
g
j
A
g
i
=
A
g
j
.
We can then partition R
1
and R
2
into equivalence
classes [g
i
] and [h
j
], respectively, obtaining R
1
=
S
g
i
l
[g
i
l
] and R
2
=
S
h
i
l
[h
i
l
]. Let us start consid-
ering the case where R
1
contains a unique equiv-
alence class: R
1
= [g
1
]. Then R
2
must contain at
least one element h
1
with A
h
1
=
A
g
1
. Moreover,
R
2
cannot contain h
0
such that h
0
6∼ h
1
, because
h
0
must be equivalent to an elementary subregion
of R
1
, by lemma 53. Then, R
2
= [h
1
]. Finally,
since A
h
g
1
=
A
R
2
=
A
R
1
=
A
k
g
1
, by lemma 2
it must be h = k. In the general case where
R
1
contains more than one equivalence class, one
can simply consider the subregions S
1
l
:
= [g
i
l
].
Clearly, for each S
1
l
there must be S
2
l
= [h
j
l
],
with |S
2
l
| = |S
1
l
|.
Remark 7. Notice that, as a consequence of the
above result, two operationally equivalent regions
R
1
, R
2
R
(G)
have the same cardinality |R
1
| =
|R
2
|.
Given two operationally equivalent regions
R
1
, R
2
G, we now have a way of defining the
notion of “running the same test”, that resorts to
the identification of a canonical isomorphism of
the two regions.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 41
Definition 42. Given two operationally equiv-
alent regions R
1
= {g
1
, g
2
, . . . , g
k
}, R
2
=
{h
1
, h
2
, . . . , h
k
} R
(G)
, let us choose a special re-
versible transformation U [[A
R
1
A
R
2
]] such
that U =
N
k
i=1
U
i
, where U
i
[[A
g
i
A
h
i
]]
is reversible for every i. We then say that R
1
is operationally equivalent to R
2
through U , and
that {B
(2)
l
}
n
l=1
[[A
R
2
C A
R
2
C]] represents the
same test as {B
(1)
l
}
n
l=1
[[A
R
1
C A
R
1
C]] if for
every 1 l n one has
B
(2)
l
= (U I
C
)B
(1)
l
(U
1
I
C
). (100)
In order to discriminate the way in which two
systems A
g
1
and A
g
2
evolve, one needs to per-
form a testing-scheme, consisting of a stimulus-
test {A
(x)
k
}
m
k=1
[[A
R
x
C A
R
x
C]]
Q
on the re-
gion R
x
3 g
x
, possibly involving an ancillary sys-
tem C, and, after the evolution step V , a control-
test {B
(x)
l
}
n
l=1
[[A
N
+
R
x
C A
N
+
R
x
C]]
Q
on the re-
gion N
+
R
x
(where x {1, 2}) and the ancilla C, in
order to detect a “response”.
Two operationally equivalent regions are ho-
mologous if there is a GUR T that interchanges
them while preserving equivalence of local tests
of finite regions. In rigorous words, we have the
following definition.
Definition 43 (Homologous regions). Let
(G, A, V
) be a GUR, and let R
1
, R
2
R
(G)
be operationally equivalent regions through T
i
[[A
R
1
A
R
2
]], such that N
+
R
1
and N
+
R
2
are op-
erationally equivalent through T
o
[[A
R
0
1
A
R
0
2
]]. We say that R
2
is homologous to R
1
if
there exists an admissible GUR (G, A, T
), such
that for all schemes ({A
(i)
k
}
m
k=1
, {B
(i)
l
}
n
l=1
)
[[A
R
i
C A
R
i
C]]
Q
× [[A
N
+
R
i
C A
N
+
R
i
C]]
Q
rep-
resenting the same pair of tests for i = 1, 2, one
has B
(1)
l
V A
(1)
k
= T
1
B
(2)
l
V A
(2)
k
T . We de-
note this relation as R
2
R
1
.
We remark that, while the relation defined
above clearly depends on V , we will generally not
make this fact explicit in the notation, as we will
always consider contexts where a given V is con-
sidered, and there will not be room for ambiguity.
On the other hand, when we want to specify the
GUR T that makes R
1
homologous to R
2
, we
write R
2
T
R
1
.
Lemma 55. If R
2
T
R
1
then R
1
T
1
R
2
.
Proof. For every scheme ({A
(i)
k
}
m
k=1
, {B
(i)
l
}
n
l=1
)
with A
(1)
k
= (T
1
i
I
C
)A
(2)
k
(T
i
I
C
) and
B
(1)
l
= (T
1
o
I
C
)B
(2)
l
(T
o
I
C
), one has
B
(1)
l
V A
(1)
k
= T
1
B
(2)
l
V A
(2)
k
T . Now, invert-
ing T on the right and T
1
on the left, one
obtains B
(2)
l
V A
(2)
k
= T B
(1)
l
V A
(1)
k
T
1
.
Lemma 56. Let V be a global rule, and let the
region R
2
be homologous to R
1
through T . Then
T
1
V T = V .
Proof. It is sufficient to consider the special case
where the test scheme is ({A
(1)
0
}, {B
(1)
0
}), with
A
(1)
0
= I
R
1
C
and B
(1)
0
= I
N
+
R
1
C
. Then, we
have A
(2)
0
= I
R
2
C
, B
(2)
0
= I
N
+
R
2
C
, and V =
T
1
V T .
Lemma 57. Let V be a global rule, and let R
2
R
1
for some suitable T . Then
T [[A
(G)
R
1
C A
(G)
R
1
C]]T
1
= [[A
(G)
R
2
C A
(G)
R
2
C]],
T [[A
(G)
N
+
R
1
C A
(G)
N
+
R
1
C]]T
1
= [[A
(G)
N
+
R
2
C A
(G)
N
+
R
2
C]].
Proof. Let us choose the test scheme as
({A
(1)
k
}
m
k=1
, {B
(1)
0
}), with B
(1)
0
= I
R
0
1
C
. Then,
we have B
(2)
0
= I
R
0
2
C
, and
V A
(1)
k
= T
1
V A
(2)
k
T
=T
1
V (T
i
I
C
)A
(1)
k
(T
1
i
I
C
)T
=T
1
V T T
1
(T
i
I
C
)A
(1)
k
(T
1
i
I
C
)T
=V T
1
(T
i
I
C
)A
(1)
k
(T
1
i
I
C
)T ,
where in the last equality we used the result of
lemma 56. If we now invert V to the left on both
sides, we obtain
A
(1)
k
= T
1
(T
i
I
C
)A
(1)
k
(T
1
i
I
C
)T ,
and finally
T A
(1)
k
T
1
=(T
i
I
C
)A
(1)
k
(T
1
i
I
C
) = A
(2)
k
.
A similar argument leads us to conclude that
T B
(1)
k
T
1
=(T
o
I
C
)B
(1)
k
(T
1
o
I
C
) = B
(2)
k
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 42
We remark that, straightforwardly,
(R
2
R
1
) (A
R
1
=
A
R
2
). (101)
Now, the discrimination of systems g
1
and g
2
is successful if there exists a region R
1
3 g
1
such
that for any operationally equivalent region R
2
3
g
2
, the region R
2
is not homologous to R
1
. In
precise terms, we have the following definition.
Definition 44 (Absolute discrimination). The
evolution given by the global rule V discriminates
two systems g
1
, g
2
G if for any GUR T there
exists a region R
1
, containing g
1
, for which there
is no region R
2
, containing g
2
, that is homologous
to R
1
through T , with g
1
T
g
2
.
In simple words, the evolution given by the
global rule V allows for discrimination of the two
systems g
1
, g
2
G if there exists a test that gives
different probabilities depending on whether it is
applied at g
1
or at g
2
, or if the tests that one can
run on R
1
cannot be performed on any region R
2
containing g
2
, or viceversa.
Now, the notion of discrimination of systems g
1
and g
2
with respect to a third system e is given
as follows.
Definition 45 (Relative discrimination). The
evolution V discriminates two systems g
1
, g
2
G
relatively to a reference system e, with e G, if
for every T there exists a region R
1
, containing
{g
1
, e}, for which there is no region R
2
, contain-
ing {g
2
, e}, homologous to R
1
through T with
e
T
e and g
1
T
g
2
.
We can now require the evolution described
by a global rule to be homogeneous by a precise
statement.
Principle 1 (Homogeneity). The global rule V
discriminates any two systems g
1
6= g
2
G, rela-
tively to an arbitrary reference system e G, but
not absolutely.
Before providing a convenient restatement of
the principle, we analyse some of its aspects and
consequences. In the first place, the principle
says that if we do not choose a reference element
e G, every two systems g
1
and g
2
cannot be
discriminated. If we take the negation of defini-
tion 44, we obtain a straightforward consequence
of homogeneity.
Lemma 58. Let V satisfy the homogeneity prin-
ciple 1. For every pair g
1
, g
2
G, there exists
T such that for every choice of region R
1
3
g
1
, there exists an operationally equivalent re-
gion R
2
3 g
2
through T
i
[[A
R
1
A
R
2
]] such
that also N
+
R
1
and N
+
R
2
are operationally equiv-
alent through T
o
[[A
R
0
1
A
R
0
2
]], and for all
schemes ({A
(i)
k
}
m
k=1
, {B
(i)
l
}
n
l=1
) representing the
same tests for i = 1, 2, one has B
(1)
l
V A
(1)
k
=
T B
(2)
l
V A
(2)
k
T
1
.
Proof. The statement follows negating defini-
tion 44.
We can now draw a first non trivial conse-
quence from the statement of principle 1.
Lemma 59. For a homogeneous GUR
(G, A, V
), all local systems A
g
for g G
are operationally equivalent.
Proof. Let us consider two elements g
1
, g
2
G.
As a consequence of the homogeneity principle 1,
for the special choice R
1
= {g
1
}, there exists
R
2
3 g
2
such that R
2
{g
1
} for a suitable T .
Now, by lemma 54, it must be |R
2
| = |{g
1
}| = 1,
i.e. R
2
= {g
2
}. Thus, we have
A
g
2
=
A
g
1
.
Corollary 15. If the region R
2
containing g
2
is
homologous to {g
1
} through T , then R
2
= {g
2
},
and
T
1
[[A
(G)
g
1
C A
(G)
g
1
C]]T = [[A
(G)
g
2
C A
(G)
g
2
C]].
(102)
Proof. By the proof of lemma 59 one has that
R
2
= g
2
. The thesis then follows from lemma 57.
The second result that we prove is a technical
lemma that will play a crucial role in the following
results.
Lemma 60. Let (G, A, V
) satisfy the homo-
geneity requirement. Then for every region R one
has A
R
=
N
xR
A
g
x
=
A
⊗|R|
0
, where A
0
=
A
g
for
every g G.
Proof. By lemma 59 we know that for every g
G one has A
g
=
A
0
. The remaining part of the
statement thus follows straightforwardly.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 43
Lemma 61. Let V be non trivial and satisfy the
homogeneity requirement, and R
2
R
1
. Then
|R
1
| = |R
2
|.
Proof. This follows from lemmas 54 and 60, since
R
1
and R
2
are operationally equivalent by defi-
nition.
Let now g
1
and g
2
be an arbitrary pair of sys-
tems in G, and V a homogeneous GUR. By the
homogeneity principle 1, there exists T such that
for every region R
1
3 g
1
there is a region R
2
3 g
2
homologous through T to R
1
. The set of these
transformations is denoted as T
V
, i.e.
T
V
:
= {T | g
1
, g
2
G
: R
1
3 g
1
R
2
3 g
2
, R
2
T
R
1
}.
Lemma 62. Let V satisfy homogeneity, and let
T T
V
. Then there exists a permutation π :
G G such that if R
2
T
R
1
it is
R
2
= π(R
1
) (103)
Proof. By definition, if T T
V
there exist
g
1
, g
2
G such that for every S
1
3 g
1
there
is S
2
3 g
2
such that S
2
T
S
1
. Let now
R
2
T
R
1
, and f
1
R
1
. Consider the finite
region V
1
:
= {f
1
, g
1
}. Then there is a region
V
2
3 g
2
such that V
2
T
V
1
, and by lemma 61,
one has |V
2
| = |V
1
| = 2. Consequently, it must
be V
2
= {f
2
, g
2
}. Moreover, since we know that
g
2
T
g
1
, by definitions 41, 42, and 43, it is
f
2
T
f
1
. Thus, for every f
1
R
1
there is a
unique f
2
R
2
such that f
2
T
f
1
. We then
define π : G G by setting π(f
1
)
:
= f
2
. By
lemma 55 the map π is both injective and surjec-
tive, and thus it is a permutation of G.
In the following, given T T
V
, we will de-
note T = T
π
where π is the permutation of G in
lemma 62.
Lemma 63. Let (G, A, V
) be a homogeneous
GUR, and π Π
V
. Then the GUR T
π
is unique.
Proof. Let T
π
, S
π
T
V
correspond to the same
permutation π. Let a [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
QR
. Then by
lemma 28 one has a = A
e
G
0
, with A [[A
G
C
A
G
C]]
QR
. Thus
(S
π
T
1
π
)
a = [(S
π
T
1
π
)
I
C
]A
e
G
0
= (T
1
π
S
π
I
C
)A
(S
1
π
T
π
I
C
)e
G
0
,
where G
0
= G h
0
and A
h
0
=
C. Now, by defi-
nition
(S
π
I
C
)A
(S
1
π
I
C
)
= (T
π
I
C
)A
(T
1
π
I
C
)
= (T
i
I
C
)A
(T
1
i
I
C
),
which implies
(S
π
T
1
π
)
a = a.
Since the latter holds for every C and every a, we
conclude that S
π
= T
π
.
Corollary 16. The set T
V
= {T
π
} is a repre-
sentation of a group Π
V
= {π | T
π
T
V
} of
permutations of G.
We can summarise the above results as follows.
For every pair g
1
, g
2
there exists a reversible map
π : G G such that π(g
1
) = g
2
and a reversible
transformation T
π
of [[A
G
]]
Q
such that T
1
π
·T
π
is
an automorphism of [[A
G
A
G
]]
Q
and for every
R G and every system C
[[A
(G)
R
C A
(G)
R
C]]
Q
= T
1
π
[[A
(G)
π(R)
C A
(G)
π(R)
C]]
Q
T
π
,
and T
π
leaves the GUR V invariant, i.e.
T
1
π
V T
π
= V .
The transformations π clearly form a group Π
V
whose action Π
V
× G G is transitive.
We now proceed considering the second part of
the homogeneity principle, i.e. the statement that
discrimination of every pair g
1
6= g
2
is possible
relative to some third element e G. The main
consequence is that the action Π
V
× G G is
free.
Lemma 64. Let V satisfy the homogeneity prin-
ciple 1. If e 6= π Π
V
, there is no element g of
G such that π(g) = g.
Proof. Let T
π
T
V
. Suppose that there is
g G such that π(g) = g. Then for every re-
gion R
1
3 g, the region R
2
:
= π(R
1
) contains g
and one has R
2
T
R
1
, with g
T
g. This is
in contradiction with definition 45, i.e. with the
homogeneity principle 1.
Corollary 17. Let Π
V
be the group of permu-
tations of G such that T
V
is a representation of
Π
V
. The action of Π
V
on G is regular.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 44
We can now summarise all the results that
we drew from homogeneity as follows: for every
g
1
, g
2
G there exists a permutation π of G such
that π(g
1
) = g
2
, and a GUR T
π
of [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
such
that for every R R
(G
0
)
and C
[[A
(G)
R
C A
(G)
R
C]]
Q
= T
1
π
[[A
(G)
π(R)
C A
(G)
π(R)
C]]
Q
T
π
, (104)
and T
π
leaves the evolution invariant, i.e.
T
1
π
V T
π
= T .
The transformations π form a group Π
V
that acts
regularly (i.e. transitively and freely) on G.
Now, it is clear that, chosen e G, the ele-
ments of G can be identified with the elements
of Π
V
, as the action of Π
V
on G is regular.
In other therms, G is a principal homogeneous
space for Π
V
, and there is a bijection Π
V
G.
However, the homogeneity principle implies an
even stronger result: the set G can be seen as
the set of vertices of a special Cayley graph of
Π
V
. The following arguments, largely inspired to
Refs. [25, 46], make the mentioned result rigor-
ous.
As a consequence of homogeneity, one has
π(g) π(g
0
) g g
0
. (105)
In other words, N
±
π(g)
= π(N
±
g
) for π Π
V
, as
can be checked starting from the definition of N
±
g
.
The proof is provided in Appendix D.
Let now g G and π Π
V
such that π(e) = g.
One can then label the elements g
0
N
±
g
by
π
1
(g
0
) N
±
e
= {h
±1
i
}
k
i=1
. Notice that for the
moment we have no reason to claim that k < .
We will associate all the pairs (g, g
0
) E with
the color h
i
if g = π(e) and g
0
= π(h
i
) for
some π Π
V
2
. This construction enriches the
graph Γ(G, E), which becomes a vertex-transitive
coloured directed graph, with colours correspond-
ing to the labels h
i
N
+
e
Given two elements g, g
0
G, a path p from g
to g
0
is an array of elements p = (g
1
, g
2
, . . . , g
k
)
2
In principle, the colour of an edge (g, g
0
) might
be ambiguously defined if there existed two permuta-
tions π, σ Π
V
such that π
1
(g) = σ
1
(g) = e and
π
1
(g
0
), σ
1
(g
0
) N
±
e
, but π
1
(g
0
) 6= σ
1
(g
0
). How-
ever, due to lemma 64, this is never the case, since it
would imply that σπ
1
(g
0
) 6= g
0
, and thus σπ
1
6= e, but
[σπ
1
](g) = σ(e) = g.
G
×k
such that, setting g
0
:
= g and g
k+1
:
= g
0
,
one has
0 i k (g
i
g
i+1
) (g
i+1
g
i
).
The lenght of a path p, denoted (p) is k +1 if p
G
×k
. In the following we will restrict attention
to the case where Γ(G, E) is connected, i.e. for
every two elements g, g
0
G there exists a path
from g to g
0
. The set of paths from g to g
0
will
be denoted by p
+
g,g
0
. We can now introduce the
graph metric of Γ(G, E) as follows. Let g, g
0
G.
Then we define
d
Γ
(g, g
0
)
:
= min
pp
+
g,g
0
(p)
We remark that d
Γ
(g, g
0
) = d
Γ
[π(g), π(g
0
)] for all
π Π
V
, since g
1
, . . . , g
k
is a path from g to g
0
if
and only if π(g
1
), . . . , π(g
k
) is a path from π(g)
to π(g
0
) due to condition (105).
We now use the alphabet N
+
e
N
e
to form
arbitrary words, obtaining a free group F: com-
position corresponds to word juxtaposition, with
the empty word λ representing the identity, and
the formal rule h
i
h
1
i
= h
1
i
h
i
= λ. An element
w = h
p
1
i
1
h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
n
i
n
of F —with p
j
{−1, 1}
thus corresponds to a path on the graph, where
the symbol h
1
i
N
e
denotes a backwards step
along the arrow h
i
. For every h
p
1
i
1
h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
m
i
m
=
w F , one has w
1
= h
p
m
i
m
. . . h
p
2
i
2
h
p
1
i
1
.
The action M : F × G G of words w =
h
p
1
i
1
. . . h
p
m1
i
m1
h
p
m
i
m
F on elements g G can be
defined as follows
M(w, g) = M(h
p
1
i
1
h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
m
i
m
, g)
:
= M[h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
m
i
m
, M(h
p
1
i
1
, g)],
where the action of h
i
S on the elements g G
is defined as M(h
i
, g) = g
0
if there exists π Π
V
such that π
1
(g) = e and π
1
(g
0
) = h
i
, while
M(h
1
i
, g) = g
0
if there exists π Π
V
such that
π
1
(g) = h
i
and π
1
(g
0
) = e
3
. In the following
we will use the shortcut
gw
:
= M(w, g).
3
The action is well defined. Suppose indeed that there
are two elements f, f
0
both satisfying the definition of
M(h
i
, g). This means that there exist π, σ such that
π
1
(g) = σ
1
(g) = e, while π
1
(f) = σ
1
(f
0
) = h
i
.
However, according to lemma 64, the first condition im-
plies that σ = π. By the same lemma, the second condi-
tion then implies that f = f
0
. A similar argument shows
that M (h
1
i
, g) is well defined.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 45
This notation is particularly handy, since
g(h
p
1
i
1
h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
m
i
m
) = (gh
p
1
i
1
)h
p
2
i
2
. . . h
p
m
i
m
.
For every w F , and for every g G and
for every permutation π Π
V
, we now show that
π(gw) = π(g)w. The first step consists in proving
the result for w = h
±1
i
. Let g
0
= gh
i
, namely by
definition σ
1
(g) = e and σ
1
(g
0
) = h
i
for some
(unique) σ π
V
. By Eq. (105) it is π(g) π(g
0
).
Moreover, if we define f
:
= π(g) and f
0
:
= π(g
0
)
we have
h
i
= σ
1
(g
0
) = σ
1
π
1
(f
0
),
e = σ
1
(g) = σ
1
π
1
(f),
namely f
0
= fh
i
. This implies
π(gh
i
) = π(g
0
) = π(g)h
i
. (106)
Similarly, if g
0
= gh
1
i
by definition σ
1
(g) = h
i
and σ
1
(g
0
) = e for some (unique) σ π
V
. Thus,
setting again f
:
= π(g) and f
0
:
= π(g
0
), we have
h
i
= σ
1
(g) = σ
1
π
1
(f),
e = σ
1
(g
0
) = σ
1
π
1
(f
0
),
namely f
0
= fh
1
i
, and
π(gh
1
i
) = π(g
0
) = π(g)h
1
i
. (107)
Notice that the last result implies that for every
pair f, g G, given π Π
V
such that π(f ) = g,
there is a bijection N
±
f
N
±
g
, given by
N
±
π(g)
= π(N
±
g
). (108)
One can now prove that π(fw) = π(f)w by in-
duction on the length l(w) of the word w. Indeed,
we know that it is true for l(w) = 1. Suppose now
that for l(w) = n 1 one has π(fw) = π(f)w,
and consider w
0
with l(w
0
) = n. Then w
0
= wh
p
i
with l(w) = n 1 and p = ±1. We have
π(fw
0
) = π(fwh
p
i
) = π[(fw)h
p
i
]
= π(fw)h
p
i
= π(f)wh
p
i
= π(f)w
0
,
where the induction hypothesis is used in the
fourth equality.
Let us now suppose that for some f G and
some word w F one has fw = f . Then for
every f
0
G one can take π such that π(f) = f
0
,
thus obtaining
f
0
w = π(f )w = π(f w) = π(f) = f
0
.
Thus, if a path w F is closed starting from
f G, then it is closed also starting from any
other g G.
We can now easily see that the subset R of F
corresponding to words r such that gr = g for
all g G is a normal subgroup. Indeed, R is a
subgroup because the juxtaposition of two words
s, s
0
R is again a word ss
0
R, and for every
word s R also s
1
R. To prove that R is nor-
mal in F we just show that it coincides with its
normal closure, i.e. for every w F and every r
R, we have wrw
1
R. Indeed, defining for arbi-
trary g the element g
0
:
= gw, we have g
0
w
1
= g,
and thus gwrw
1
= g
0
rw
1
= g
0
w
1
= g, namely
wrw
1
R.
We thus identified a normal subgroup R con-
taining all the words r corresponding to closed
paths. If one takes the quotient F/R, one obtains
a group whose elements are equivalence classes of
words in F . If we label an arbitrary element of
G by e, it is clear that the elements of G are in
one-to-one correspondence with the vertices of G,
since for every g G there is one and only one
class in F/R whose elements lead from e to g.
We can then write g = w for every w F such
that w represents a path leading from e to g. No-
tice that the elements of F/R, i.e. equivalence
classes of words [w]
R
, correspond to elements of
G, i.e. for every g G there is a unique class
[w]
R
such that g = [w]
R
. The criterion for class
membership of words is very simple: w g iff w
connects the vertex e G to the vertex g G.
As a consequence of the above arguments, we
can now show that for every π Π
V
and for every
g = [w]
R
G, one has π(g) = [sw]
R
for a fixed
word s F . Indeed, consider g
0
= [w
0
]
R
. Let
[w
0
]
R
= π(g
0
). Then w
0
= w
0
w
1
0
w
0
= sw
0
, with
s
:
= w
0
w
1
0
, and π(g
0
) = [sw
0
]
R
. Let now f G.
We can always find t F so that f = [w
0
t]
R
,
e.g. by setting t
:
= w
1
0
z, f = [z]
R
. Then we have
π(f) = π([w
0
t]
R
) = π(g
0
t) = π(g
0
)t = [sw
0
t]
R
=
[sz]
R
, where we use the definition π(k)r
:
= [xr]
R
with π(k) = [x]
R
. This definition clearly makes
sense, since when [a]
R
= [b]
R
and [r]
R
= [u]
R
,
also [ar]
R
= [bu]
R
.
In technical terms, the graph Γ(G, E) =
Γ(G, S) is the Cayley graph of the group G =
F/R. Homogeneity thus implies that the set G is
a group G that can be presented as G = hS|Ri,
where S is the set of generators of G and R is the
group of relators. In the following, if h
i
= h
1
i
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 46
we will draw an undirected edge to represent h
i
.
The presentation can be chosen by arbitrarily di-
viding S into S
+
S and S
:
= S
1
+
in such a
way that S
+
S
= S. The above arbitrariness
is inherent the very notion of group presentation
and corresponding Cayley graph, and is exploited
in the literature, in particular in the definition of
isotropy [25, 57].
For convenience of the reader we remind the
definition of Cayley graph. Given a group G and
a set S
+
of generators of the group, the Cayley
graph Γ(G, S
+
) is defined as the colored directed
graph having vertex set G, edge set {(g, gh) | g
G, h S
+
}, and a color assigned to each gener-
ator h S
+
. Notice that a Cayley graph is reg-
ular—i.e. each vertex has the same degree—and
vertex-transitive—i.e. all vertices are equivalent,
in the sense that the graph automorphism group
acts transitively upon its vertices. The Cayley
graphs of a group G are in one to one correspon-
dence with its presentations, with Γ(G, S
+
) cor-
responding to the presentation hS
+
|Ri.
7 Locality
If a GUR were to represent a physical law, we
would like that, in order to determine it, it is
sufficient to test it in a finite region and for a fi-
nite amount of time. This possibility is granted
by homogeneity in conjunction with a second
principle—locality—to which the present section
is devoted. The locality requirement can be
phrased in simple words by stipulating that in
order to calculate the effects of a physical law, i)
it is possible to adopt a reductionist procedure,
decomposing an arbitrary system into elementary
parts and then calculating its evolution by evolv-
ing every part separately, considering only pair-
wise interactions between parts, and ii) if the re-
duction is operated, only finite systems will be
involved in the calculation for every elementary
part.
In the present section we introduce the precise
statement of the locality principle, and analyse its
main consequences. In order to make this notion
independent of homogeneity, we formulate it for
general admissible GURs. In particular, this im-
plies that the mathematical statement of locality
alone will not allow for determination of a local
GUR by observation of a finite region.
Before giving a formal definition, we provide a
few heuristic steps leading to the final formula-
tion. Let us start considering an admissible GUR
(G, A, V
), with uniformly bounded neighbour-
hood, namely such that there exists k < so
that for every g G it is |N
±
g
| k. We remark
that, since |N
±
g
| k, it is |P
±
g
| k
2
. This also
implies that the transformations S
0
g
are transfor-
mations of finitely many systems.
In the remainder, we will often omit the labels
0, 1 on the wires in diagrams, and adopt the con-
vention that the upper half is labelled 0 and the
lower one 1.
Now, reminding Eq. (92), given a
[[
¯
A
(G)
R
C]]
QR
, one has
[(V
a)
(N
R
,1)C
] = [{(V
R
I
C
)a}
(N
R
,1)C
]
= [{(S
0†
N
R
I
C
)a}
(N
R
,1)C
].
Thus, we have
N
R
V
R
R
=
ψ
P
R
S
0
N
R
R
P
R
\R
e
N
R
N
R
e
.
(109)
Notice that, by admissibility of the GUR V , and
thanks to the no-restriction hypothesis,
V
R
[[A
N
R
A
R
]]
1
.
Moreover, the GUR V can be equivalently de-
fined starting from its action on [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, by set-
ting V
[a
R
]
:
= [(V
R
a)
N
R
]. Indeed, following
this definition, one can prove that V is right-
invertible, by the argument discussed in Ap-
pendix E. We remark that the construction of the
inverse provides a new GUR W .
As a consequence, we have that W
V
=
V
W
= I
G
for some GUR W , and thus W =
V
1
. We want to stress here that in proving
this result we only use properties (88), (89), (94)
and (97) of S
0
g
, derived in section 5.4, along with
uniform boundedness of the neighbourhoods for
the GUR V (see Appendix E for the details).
Let us now abstract our focus from the situa-
tion where a GUR (G, A, V
) is given. Instead,
we will suppose that, given the pair (G, A), a fi-
nite neighbourhood N
+
g
G is defined for every
g G, and for f G we set
N
f
:
= {h G | f N
+
h
}.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 47
For X R
(G)
we then define N
±
X
:
=
S
gX
N
±
g
,
and the sets P
±
g
are then defined exactly as for a
GUR. Finally, we suppose that a family of maps
S
0
g
is defined, with the properties (88) and (89),
and an analogue of (94) and (97).
Definition 46 (Local rule). A k-local rule
(N
+
, A, S
0
) on G is i) a map N
+
: G R
(G)
that associates g G with a finite region N
+
g
R
(G)
such that |N
+
g
|, |N
g
| k for every g G;
ii) a map S
0
: g 7→ S
0
g
, where S
0
g
are maps in
[[A
(N
+
g
,0)
A
(g,1)
A
(N
+
g
,0)
A
(g,1)
]]
1
with the follow-
ing properties for every f, g G and R, S R
(G)
:
1. S
0
g
S
0
g
= I
A
N
+
g
A
g
;
2. S
0
g
S
0
f
= S
0
f
S
0
g
;
3. for every C [[A
(R,0)(S,1)
C A
(R,0)(S,1)
C]]
P
R
\N
+
S
S
0
N
R
S
N
+
N
R
S
\R
S
0
N
R
S
P
R
\N
+
S
N
+
S R
C
R
N
+
S
C C
N
R S S
N
R
S\N
R
N
R
\S S\N
R
=
P
R
\N
+
S
N
+
S
C
0
N
+
S
C C
N
R
N
R
S\N
R
, (110)
where S
0
X
:
=
Q
gX
S
0
g
for every X G.
In the following, we will often omit the sub-
script X in S
0
X
in the diagrams, since X corre-
sponds to the label of the lower half wires. More-
over, in order to make the equations lighter, from
now on we will always write or draw transfor-
mations and effects that do not involve explicitly
the external system C, however it will always be
assumed that the conditions hold also locally on
extended systems, unless explicitly stated other-
wise.
Remark 8. Notice that for a transformation C
of the form C
0
I
(R\R
0
,0)(S\S
0
,1)
, due to the def-
inition of S
0
N
R
S
and the property 2 of S
0
g
, one
has that
P
R
\N
+
S
N
+
S
C
0
N
+
S
C C
N
R
N
R
S\N
R
=
P
R
\N
+
S
N
+
S
\N
+
S
0
N
+
S
0
C
0
0
N
+
S
0
C C
N
R
0
N
R
0
N
R
\N
R
0
S\N
R
=
[P
R
N
+
S
]\[P
R
0
N
+
S
0
]
P
R
0
\N
+
S
0
S
0
N
+
N
R
0
S
0
\R
0
S
0
P
R
0
\N
+
S
0
N
+
S
0
R
0
C
0
R
0
N
+
S
0
C C
N
R
0
S
0
S
0
N
R
0
S
0
\N
R
0
N
R
0
\S
0
S
0
\N
R
0
[N
R
S]\[N
R
0
S
0
]
.
The first property that we prove is the follow-
ing.
Lemma 65. Given a local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) on
G, the following identities hold:
1. For every S R
(G)
, and every A [[A
S
C
A
S
C]],
(N
+
S
,0)
S
0
N
S
(N
+
S
,0)
S
0
N
S
(N
+
S
,0)
C
A
C
(S,1) (S,1) (S,1) (S,1)
=
(N
+
S
,0)
A
+
(N
+
S
,0)
C C
(S,1)
; (111)
2. for every R R
(G)
and every B [[A
R
C
A
R
C]]
(P
R
,0)
S
0
N
R
(P
R
\R,0)
S
0
N
R
(P
R
,0)
(R,0)
B
(R,0)
C C
(N
R
,1) (N
R
,1) (N
R
,1)
=
(P
R
,0)
C
B
C
(N
R
,1) (N
R
,1)
. (112)
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 48
Proof. The equalities follow taking S = and
R = in Eq. (110), respectively.
Remark 9. Given a local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) we
define the forward and backward evolution of lo-
cal transformations F [[A
R
C A
R
C]] for
a finite region R R
(G)
through the expres-
sions (111) and (112), as follows
[V
±
L
(F )]
N
±
R
C
:
= [F
±
]
N
±
R
C
. (113)
Now, once we established the notion of a local
rule and its application to local transformations,
we can define the property of a global rule of be-
ing reducible to a local rule.
Definition 47 (Reduction to a local rule). We
say that the GUR (G, A, V
) is reducible to a
local rule if there exists a k-local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
)
for some k < such that for every R R
(G)
and
every F [[A
R
C A
R
C]]
(V I
C
)F (V
1
I
C
) = V
L
(F ) I
G\N
R
,
(V
1
I
C
)F (V I
C
) = V
+
L
(F ) I
G\N
+
R
.
(114)
We now prove the two main results of this sec-
tion, which relate local rules and GURs in a one-
to-one correspondence.
Theorem 9. Every local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) on G
identifies a GUR (G
0
, A, W
), with G
0
= G ×
{0, 1}, and W
1
= S
G
W S
G
.
Proof. First of all, one can define the linear maps
W
C
on [[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
LR
as follows. For a
ZC
[[
¯
A
G
¯
C]]
LR
,
with Z = (R, 0) (S, 1), we set
W
[a
ZC
]
:
= [a
(N
R
,0)(N
+
S
,1)C
],
where
˜
N
+
N
R
S
e
S\N
R
e
N
R
a
C
N
+
S
P
R
\N
+
S
e
\
N
R
S
e
:
=
˜
N
+
N
R
S
S
\
N
R
S
e
S\N
R
P
R
\N
+
S
S
0
N
+
N
R
S
\R
e
N
R
N
+
S R
a
C
N
+
S
N
R S
P
R
\N
+
S
S\N
R
N
R
\S
e
\
N
R
S
˜
N
+
N
R
S
e
.
We omitted the subscript for S and S
0
, as the
systems on which the transformations act are
clear from the context. Finally,
˜
N
+
X
is a short-
hand for N
+
X
\X, and
b
X for X \N
+
X
. Writing a =
A
e, for A [[A
(R,0)(S,1)
C A
(R,0)(S,1)
C]],
and using Eq. (110), one can easily check that
the effect a
is actually in [[
¯
A
(N
R
,0)(N
+
S
,1)
¯
C]]. We
remark that the map W
is well defined: for
a e
W
[a
ZC
], with W = (W
0
, 0) (W
1
, 1),
and W
0
R = W
1
S = , one has
W
[(a e
W
)
(RW
0
,0)(SW
1
,1)C
] = W
[a
ZC
].
The above identity is verified exploiting
Eq. (110), along with the identity in Re-
mark 8. As to reversibility, for [a
ZC
] with
Z = (R, 0) (S, 1), one can define
Z
[a
ZC
]
:
= [a
+
(N
+
R
,0)(N
S
,1)C
],
where
\
N
+
S
R
e
P
S
\N
+
R
e
N
+
R
a
+
C
N
S
R\N
S
e
˜
N
+
N
S
R
e
:
=
\
N
R
S
S
˜
N
+
N
S
R
e
P
S
\N
+
R
S
0
N
+
N
S
R
\S
N
S
\R
e
N
+
R S R
a
C
N
S R S
R\N
S
N
S
\R
N
+
N
S
R
\S
e
˜
N
+
N
S
R
\
N
R
S
e
,
and, similarly to what was done for W , check
that Z
is well defined. One can now verify that
W
Z
= Z
W
= I
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
. The above observa-
tions show that W
and Z
= W
1
act isomet-
rically on [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, since
ka
RC
k
sup
= kZ
W
a
RC
k
sup
kW
a
RC
k
sup
ka
RC
k
sup
,
ka
RC
k
sup
= kW
Z
a
RC
k
sup
kZ
a
RC
k
sup
ka
RC
k
sup
.
Being isometric, both W
and W
1
preserve
Cauchy sequences and their equivalence classes.
As a consequence, W
and W
1
can be uniquely
extended to invertible isometries of [[
¯
A
G
0
]]
QR
,
with Z
= W
†−1
. Let now ρ [[A
G
0
C]], and
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 49
a
(R,0)(S,1)C
[[
¯
A
G
0
¯
C]]
LR
. Then
(a
(R,0)(S,1)C
|
ˆ
W ρ) = (W
a
(R,0)(S,1)C
|ρ)
=(S
N
R
SN
+
N
R
S
S
0†
N
R
S
a
(S,0)(T,1)C
|ρ)
=(a
(R,0)(S,1)C
|
ˆ
S
0
N
R
S
ˆ
S
N
R
SN
+
N
R
S
ρ)
=(a|[
ˆ
S
0
N
R
S
ˆ
S
N
R
SN
+
N
R
S
ρ]
|(N
R
,0)(N
+
S
,1)C
),
and clearly this implies that
ˆ
W ρ
|(R,0)(S,1)
is a
state for every R, S R
(G)
. Then
ˆ
W [[A
G
C]]
[[A
G
C]]. The same argument holds for
ˆ
W
1
,
thus
ˆ
W [[A
G
C]] = [[A
G
C]]. Let now A
T C
[[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L
, with T = (R, 0) (S, 1). One
can evaluate
ˆ
W
1
A
T C
ˆ
W by dually evaluating
W
A
T C
W
1
. The calculation is a straightfor-
ward application of Eq. (110), and shows that
ˆ
W
1
A
T C
ˆ
W [[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L
. The same argu-
ment holds for
ˆ
W A
T C
ˆ
W
1
, and thus
ˆ
W
1
[[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L
ˆ
W = [[A
G
C A
G
C]]
L
.
All the above observations prove that W is a UR.
Finally, being constructed from local transforma-
tions, one can easily check that the family {W
C
|
C Sys} is an admissible UR. This concludes the
proof that (G
0
, A, W
) is a GUR. Now, comparing
the equations defining a
±
(N
±
R
,0)(N
S
,1)C
, one can
easily conclude that Z = W
1
= S
G
W S
G
.
Theorem 10. Let (N
+
, A, S
0
) be a local rule on
G. Then the GUR (G
0
, A, W
), with G
0
= G ×
{0, 1} in theorem 9, is of the form W = V V
1
,
where (G, A, V
) is reducible to (N
+
, A, S
0
).
The detailed proof can be found in Appendix F.
The properties used in the proof are (88), (89),
(94), and (97). The first two are required as
items 1 and 2 in the definition 46 of a local rule,
while the remaining two are a consequence of
item 3 as shown by lemma 65.
In the case of a homogeneous update rule, does
the existence of a local rule allow one to determine
the full (G, A, V
) by local tests? One would in-
tuitively expect that the answer is positive, since
S
0
g
= S
0
e
are the same for every g G, by virtue
of homogeneity, and thus, knowing S
0
e
, one could
calculate the action of V through Eq. (112). On
the other hand, after giving the question another
thought, one can realise that calculating the ac-
tion of V through the maps V
±
L
requires another
piece of information besides knowing S
0
e
. Actu-
ally, determining the cellular automaton with lo-
cal tests also requires knowledge of the regions
N
+
R
for every R R
(G)
—or, in other words,
knowledge of the structure of the graph of in-
fluence relations. This information is indeed nec-
essary in order to know how to correctly calcu-
late the transformation V
±
L
(A
R
) for a given re-
gion R. Indeed, it might happen that knowledge
of finitely many closed paths from the elements
g R is not sufficient to reconstruct all the new
closed paths that appear as the size of the region
R increases. This means that one needs infinitely
many rules to identify systems in N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
. How-
ever, this is not the case if closed paths in the
graph of influence relations can be decomposed
into elementary closed paths having a uniformly
bounded size, let us say by a constant length l. In
this case, knowledge of local rules and of the local
structure of the graph up to some finite distance
l is sufficient to calculate the action of V in an
arbitrary finite region. This is the reason for the
following definition.
Definition 48 (Decomposability into bounded
regions). We say that a global update rule
(G, A, V
) is decomposable into bounded regions
if the closed paths of the influence graph of V
can be decomposed into elementary closed paths
of uniformly bounded length.
We are finally in position to formulate the lo-
cality principle, which can be thought of as the re-
quirement that finite, local information is needed
in order to reconstruct the update rule.
Principle 2 (Locality). The GUR (G, A, V
) is
reducible to a local rule and decomposable into
bounded regions.
8 Cellular Automata
The principles of homogeneity and locality single
out the special class of global rules that we will
call cellular automata.
Definition 49. Let (G, A, V
) be a global up-
date rule obeying the principles of homogeneity
and locality. We say that (G, A, V
) is a cellular
automaton.
Notice that the influence graph of a cellular
automaton is the Cayley graph of a finitely pre-
sented group, i.e. a group that is finitely gener-
ated and can be presented through finitely many
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 50
relators. This fact has the very important con-
sequence that every cellular automaton defines
a Cayley graph that is quasi-isometric to some
smooth Riemannian manifold of dimension d 4
(see [47], sec. IV pag. 90).
An important remark is in order. Thanks to
homogeneity, one can easily show that the local
rule S
0
g
for a cellular automaton on the Cayley
graph Γ(G, S
+
) has the property that S
0
g
= S
0
e
G
for every g G. Thus, cellular automata can be
identified by their Cayley graph Γ(G, S
+
) and by
a reversible transformation S
0
e
G
[[A
N
+
e
G
A
e
G
A
N
+
e
G
A
e
G
]]
1
.
8.1 Results
We now prove two important theorems regarding
cellular automata. The first one shows that, in
order to obey the properties of homogeneity and
locality, a cellular automaton cannot be in the
quasi-local algebra.
Theorem 11. Let |G| = . The homogeneous
and local cellular automaton V is an element of
[[A
G
A
G
]]
Q1
if and only if it is trivial: V =
I
G
.
Proof. Let V be in the quasi-local algebra, and
V
nR
n
be a sequence of local transformations in
the class of V . Then for ε > 0 there exists n
0
such that for every n n
0
one has
kV
nR
n
V k
sup
ε.
Moreover, for π Π
V
, one has T
π
V T
1
π
= V .
Then
kV
nR
n
T
π
V T
1
π
k
sup
ε.
Since T
π
is a GUR, it is isometric and thus
kT
1
π
V
nR
n
T
π
V k
sup
= kV
nR
n
T
π
V T
1
π
k
sup
ε. (115)
Now, this implies that
kV
nR
n
T
1
π
V
nR
n
T
π
k
sup
2ε.
It is easy to prove that, if |G| = , for every
R R
(G)
there must exist π Π
V
so that R
π(R) = . Suitably choosing π, condition (115)
then takes the form
kW I I W k
sup
= kW I W W + W W I W k
sup
2kW I k
sup
ε.
Being ε arbitrary, we must conclude that W =
I , namely V
nR
n
= 1
.
The second result pertains the following types
of theory.
1. Theories with local discriminability [8, 9,
15, 58], or more generally every theory
where the algebra of transformations A
[[A
1
. . . A
n
A
1
. . . A
n
]] is generated by lo-
cal transformations, i.e. transformations of
the form
A
i
I
¯
A
i
[[A
i
A
i
]],
where
¯
A
i
is the composite system made of
all A
1
. . . A
n
except from A
i
. This class in-
cludes, among others, classical information
theory and quantum theory.
2. Theories where the algebra of transforma-
tions A [[A
1
. . . A
n
A
1
. . . A
n
]] is gener-
ated by bipartite transformations, i.e. trans-
formations of the form
A
i,j
I
¯
A
i
¯
A
j
[[A
i
A
j
A
i
A
j
]],
where
¯
A
i
¯
A
j
is the composite system made of
all A
1
. . . A
n
except from A
i
and A
j
. This
case includes the Fermionic theory as well as
real quantum theory.
In the above cases, for groups G with suitable
properties that we will immediately specify, the
admissible local rules for a cellular automaton can
be sought considering finite-dimensional systems.
In the remainder we will then restrict to the fam-
ilies of theories introduced above.
Before proving this result, we need some pre-
liminary definition and lemma.
Definition 50 (Quotient group). Let G, H be
two groups, and suppose that there exists a group
homomorphism ϕ : G H. Then H is a quo-
tient of G. If H is finite, it is called a finite
quotient of G.
The reason why we are interested in finite quo-
tients is that, under suitable assumptions that
will be made rigorous shortly, the same local rule
defines an automaton on G and an automaton on
any of its finite quotients H. This result makes
it much easier to provide unitarity conditions in
all those cases where the finite quotients of the
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 51
group G satisfy the mentioned requirements. We
now explain the hypotheses in detail, and finally
prove the main theorem.
We start remarking that if the group G has a
finite presentation
G = ha
1
, . . . , a
n
|r
1
, . . . , r
k
i,
it is straightforward to verify that any quotient
H of G has a finite presentation of the form
H = hϕ(a
1
), . . . , ϕ(a
n
)|ϕ(r
1
), . . . , ϕ(r
k
), b
1
, . . . , b
j
i,
where the new relations b
k
do not belong to the
group R, conjugate closure of {ϕ(r
1
), . . . , ϕ(r
k
)}.
When H is a quotient of G, referring to the
presentation above, we will denote by R
0
the
conjugate closure of the group generated by
{φ(r
l
)}
k
l=1
{b
m
}
j
m=1
. Moreover, the neighbour-
hoods of f in Γ(H, φ(S
+
)) will be denoted by N
f
for f H. We now state two lemmas that we use
in the following. The proofs are provided in Ap-
pendix G
Lemma 66. Let N
+
be a neighbourhood system
corresponding to the Cayley graph Γ(G, S
+
) of a
a finitely generated group G, and let H = φ(G)
be a finite quotient of G such that for every
h
a
, h
b
, h
c
, h
d
S
+
one has φ(h
a
h
1
b
) R
0
, if and
only if h
a
h
1
b
R and φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
) R
0
if
and only if h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
R.
1. N
φ(g)
= φ(N
±
g
), and |N
φ(g)
| = |N
±
g
|.
2. P
φ(g)
= φ(P
±
g
), and |P
φ(g)
| = |P
±
g
|.
3. Given f
1
, f
2
H, one can choose g
i
φ
1
(f
i
) such that N
f
1
N
f
2
= φ(N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
)
and |N
f
1
N
f
2
| = |N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
|.
4. Given f
1
, f
2
H, one can choose g
i
φ
1
(f
i
) such that P
0∓
f
2
N
f
1
= φ(P
g
2
N
±
g
1
)
and |P
0∓
f
2
N
f
1
| = |φ(P
g
2
N
±
g
1
)|.
5. If g
2
6∈ N
±
g
1
and φ(g
2
) N
φ(g
1
)
, it is P
±
g
1
N
g
2
= .
Lemma 67. In addition to the hypothe-
ses of lemma 66, let φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
)
R
0
iff h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
R for every
h
a
, h
b
, h
c
, h
d
, h
e
, h
f
S
+
. Then
1. Given f
1
, f
2
H with f
2
P
f
1
, one has
P
f
1
P
f
2
= φ(P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
), for some g
i
φ
1
(f
i
), with g
2
P
±
g
1
, and |P
f
1
P
f
2
| =
|P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
|.
2. Let g
2
6∈ P
±
g
1
and φ(g
2
) P
φ(g
1
)
. Then N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
= P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
= .
Corollary 18. Under the hypotheses of
lemma 66, the homomorphism φ is invertible on
N
±
g
and P
±
g
for every g G.
In order to make the hypotheses of lemmas 66
and 67 clearer, in Fig. 2 we show two examples
of finite quotients of the group Z
2
, the first one
satisfying the hypotheses of lemma 66 but not
those of lemma 67, and the second one satisfying
both.
(a)
(b)
(c)
Figure 2: (a) The Cayley graph of Z
2
presented as
ha, b|aba
1
b
1
i; (b) the Cayley graph of the finite
quotient of Z
2
hφ(a), φ(b)|φ(aba
1
b
1
), φ(a)
6
, φ(b)
5
i,
satisfying the hypotheses of lemma 66 but not those
of 67; (c) the Cayley graph of the finite quotient
of Z
2
hφ(a), φ(b)|φ(aba
1
b
1
), φ(a)
8
, φ(b)
7
i, satisfying
the hypotheses of both lemmas 66 and 67. Notice that
we implicitly assume that S
+
contains also a
1
and b
1
,
but we do not express the presentation accordingly, to
keep the formulas readable. In principle there should
be two extra generators c, d (and φ(c), φ(d) in the fi-
nite quotients), along with the relations ac and bd (and
φ(ac), φ(bd), accordingly).
We can now prove the following results, which
are the core of the final theorem at the end of the
section.
Lemma 68. For theories of type 1, under the
hypotheses of lemma 66, given a homogeneous
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 52
local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) with neighbourhood sys-
tem N
+
such that |N
+
e
G
| = |S
+
|, the local
rule (N
0+
, A,
˜
S
0
), with
˜
S
0
e
H
:
= S
0
e
G
is well-
defined on the Cayley graph Γ(H, φ(S
+
)), with
N
0+
φ(g)
= φ(N
+
g
). Viceversa, given a local
rule (N
0+
, A,
˜
S
0
) whose neighbourhood system
N
0+
corresponds to a Cayley graph Γ(H, φ(S
+
)),
the local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
), with S
0
e
:
=
˜
S
0
e
is
well-defined on the Cayley graph Γ(G, S
+
), with
φ(N
+
g
) = N
0+
φ(g)
Proof. We remark that, by definition of the maps
S
0
g
(see Definition 46) a given choice of S
0
e
H
is in principle compatible with every Cayley
graph with |N
e
H
| = |N
±
e
G
|, i.e. the same num-
ber of generators (we remind that S
0
g
= S
0
e
H
[[A
N
+
e
G
A
e
G
A
N
+
e
G
A
e
G
]]
1
). By lemma 66, the
cardinality of N
0+
e
H
is the same as that of N
+
e
G
.
Then
˜
S
0
e
H
= S
0
e
G
is well defined on Γ(H, φ(S
+
))
iff it is well defined on Γ(G, S
+
). What remains
to be proved is that the map
˜
S
0
e
H
= S
0
e
G
identi-
fies a local rule on the system of neighbourhoods
N
0+
—namely that Eq. (110) as well as items 1
and 2 in definition 46 hold—iff it does on the
system of neighbourhoods N
+
. Item 1 is sat-
isfied by
˜
S
0
= S
0
by definition in both cases.
As to item 2, it is trivial to verify that the only
important feature in order to decide whether it
holds in any neighbourhood system N
0+
e
H
is the
cardinality of N
0+
e
H
N
0+
f
(or N
+
e
G
N
+
g
) for every
f P
0+
e
H
(or g P
e
G
), since this identifies the
systems where both
˜
S
0
e
H
= S
0
e
G
and
˜
S
0
f
= S
0
g
act non-trivially, namely those where the prod-
ucts
˜
S
0
e
H
˜
S
0
f
or S
0
e
G
S
0
g
might not be commuta-
tive. Lemma 66 thus ensures that item 2 is sat-
isfied by
˜
S
0
iff it is by S . Let us then focus on
Eq. (110). For theories of type 1, it is sufficient
to verify that Eq. (110) holds for |R| = 1 and
|S| = 0 or |R| = 0 and |S| = 1. Both conditions
easily follow if we consider lemma 66.
Lemma 69. For theories of type 2, under the
hypotheses of lemma 67, given a homogeneous
local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) with neighbourhood sys-
tem N
+
such that |N
+
e
G
| = |S
+
|, the local
rule (N
0+
, A,
˜
S
0
), with
˜
S
0
e
H
:
= S
0
e
G
is well-
defined on the Cayley graph Γ(H, φ(S
+
)), with
N
0+
φ(g)
= φ(N
+
g
). Viceversa, given a local
rule (N
0+
, A,
˜
S
0
) whose neighbourhood system
N
0+
corresponds to a Cayley graph Γ(H, φ(S
+
)),
the local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
), with S
0
e
:
=
˜
S
0
e
is
well-defined on the Cayley graph Γ(G, S
+
), with
φ(N
+
g
) = N
0+
φ(g)
Proof. The first part of the proof proceeds ex-
actly as that of lemma 68. The non trivial part
of the proof regards the equivalence of Eq. (110)
for both S
0
on G and
˜
S
0
on H. Suppose that
S
0
defines a local rule for the neighbourhood sys-
tem N
+
g
. In theories of type 2, it is sufficient
to verify that Eq. (110) holds for regions with
|R| = 2, |S| = 0, or |R| = 1, |S| = 1, or |R| = 0,
|S| = 2. Let then R, S Γ(H, φ(S
+
)), with
R = φ(
˜
R) and S = φ(
˜
S). In the first case we have
R = {f
1
, f
2
}, with
˜
R = {g
1
, g
2
} and f
i
= φ(g
i
),
while S = . The relevant informations in or-
der to verify Eq. (110) are the cardinalities i)
|N
0−
f
1
N
0−
f
2
| and ii) |P
0−
f
1
P
0−
f
2
|. If f
2
P
0−
f
1
,
by lemma 67 we know that we can choose g
1
and g
2
so that |N
0−
f
1
N
0−
f
2
| = |N
g
1
N
g
2
| and
|P
0−
f
1
P
0−
f
2
| = |P
g
1
P
g
2
|. Thus, since Eq. (110)
holds for C [[A
(G)
˜
R
A
(G)
˜
R
]], and
A
(G)
˜
R
=
A
(H)
R
,
˜
S
0
= S
0
,
we conclude that Eq. (110) holds also for C
[[A
(H)
R
A
(H)
R
]]. On the other hand, if f
2
6∈ P
0−
f
1
,
we can calculate
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
,f
2
C
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
,f
2
in two steps.
First we apply
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
= S
0
N
g
1
, treating the system
f
2
as an external system. Reminding that f
2
6∈
P
0−
f
1
, it is N
0−
f
1
N
0−
f
2
= . By Eq. (110), that
holds for S
0
N
g
1
we then have
(P
0−
f
2
\[P
0−
f
1
f
2
],0)
(f
2
,0)
C
(f
2
,0)
(P
0−
f
1
,0)
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
(f
1
,0) (f
1
,0)
˜
S
0
N
f
1
(P
0−
f
1
,0)
(P
0−
f
1
\f
1
,0)
(N
0−
f
1
,1) (N
f
1
,1) (N
0−
f
1
,1)
(N
0−
f
2
,1)
=
(P
0−
f
1
P
0−
f
2
\f
2
,0)
(f
2
,0)
C
0
(f
2
,0)
(N
0−
f
1
,1) (N
0−
f
1
,1)
(N
0−
f
2
,1)
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 53
Then, we apply
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
2
, obtaining
(N
0−
f
1
,1)
C
0
(N
0−
f
1
,1)
(N
0−
f
2
,1)
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
2
(f
2
,0) (f
2
,0)
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
2
(N
0−
f
2
,1)
(N
0−
f
2
,1)
(P
0−
f
2
,0) (P
0−
f
2
\f
2
,0) (P
0−
f
2
,0)
(P
0−
f
1
,0)
(P
0−
f
2
\[P
0−
f
1
f
2
],0)
=
(P
0−
f
1
P
0−
f
2
,0)
(N
0−
f
1
,1)
C
00
(N
0−
f
1
,1)
(N
0−
f
2
,1) (N
0−
f
2
,1)
, (116)
where on the l.h.s. we reversed the ordering of
the wires for the sake of simplicity of the di-
agram. Overall, considering that
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
N
0−
f
2
=
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
2
=
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
2
˜
S
0
N
0−
f
1
, we then proved
Eq. (110) for the local rule
˜
S
0
f
on the neighbour-
hood scheme given by the graph Γ(H, φ(S
+
)).
In the second case, let R = f
1
= φ(g
1
), S =
f
2
= φ(g
2
). The informations that matter are
whether one can choose g
1
, g
2
so that f
2
N
0−
f
1
iff g
2
N
g
1
, and |P
0−
f
1
N
0+
f
2
| = |P
g
1
N
+
g
2
|. Again
by lemma 66, we know that the answer is posi-
tive. Then, also for |R| = |S| = 1, since Eq. (110)
holds for C [[A
(G)
(
˜
R,0)(
˜
S,1)
A
(G)
(
˜
R,0)(
˜
S,1)
]], and
A
(G)
(
˜
R,0)(
˜
S,1)
=
A
(H)
(R,0)(S,1)
,
˜
S
0
= S
0
,
we conclude that Eq. (110) holds also for C
[[A
(H)
(R,0)(S,1)
A
(H)
(R,0)(S,1)
]]. The argument for
|R| = 0, |S| = 2 is the same as for |R| = 2,
|S| = 0. For the converse, one can follow the
same argument as for the direct statement. The
only differences are that in the case |R| = 2
and |S| = 0 one might have g
2
6∈ P
g
1
while
f
2
= φ(g
2
) φ(P
g
1
) = P
0−
f
2
, and in the case
|R| = |S| = 1 it might happen that g
2
6∈ N
g
1
while f
2
N
0−
f
1
. By lemma 67, the first case
can occur only if N
+
g
1
N
+
g
2
= P
g
1
P
g
2
= ,
while by lemma 66 the second case occurs only
if P
g
1
N
+
g
2
= . In both cases, the different
structure of the neighbourhoods between G and
H does not preclude the derivation of Eq. (110)
in the case of G from the same identity for the
case of H, as one can immediately realise by di-
rect inspection of Eq. (110).
Theorem 12 (Wrapping lemma). For a theory
of type 1, under the hypotheses of lemma 66,
the local rule (N
+
, A, S
0
) defines a cellular au-
tomaton (G, A, V ) on the Cayley graph Γ(G, S
+
)
if and only if the same local rule defines a cel-
lular automaton (H, A, W ) on the Cayley graph
Γ(H, φ(S
+
)). The same is true of a theory of
type 2, under the hypotheses of lemma 67.
Proof. The thesis now easily follows from lem-
mas 68 and 69, and theorem 10.
The above result allows us, at least in theories
of the two types considered so far, and for CAs
on Cayley graphs of groups with finite quotients
satisfying the hypotheses of lemmas 66 or 67, to
reduce the classification of CAs on graphs of infi-
nite groups to that of CAs on finite groups, which
is in principle a much easier task. Moreover, once
a suitable finite quotient is found, one can simu-
late the evolution of a finite region and for a finite
number of steps considering the same evolution
on the finite wrapped graph instead of having to
consider the actual infinite graph.
9 Examples
9.1 Classical case
Classical systems d can be classified in terms of
the number d of pure states ρ
y
, y = 1, . . . , d which
coincides with the dimension of the state space
d = dim[[d]]
R
. All the pure states of a classical
system are jointly discriminable by atomic effects
a
x
, x = 1, . . . , d, i.e. (a
x
|ρ
y
) = δ
xy
. For the sake
of simplicity, we will restrict attention to classi-
cal computation, i.e. the sub-theory of classical
theory where there is only one kind of non-trivial
elementary system, the bit having d = 2, and all
other systems are composite systems of n bits,
having dimension d = 2
n
. Every effect in [[
¯
A
G
]]
Q
for an infinite system |G| = can be decom-
posed as a series of effects corresponding to finite,
arbitrarily large bit strings b
R
, with
b
R
:
= [a
R
], a = a
b
r
1
a
b
r
2
. . . a
b
r
|R|
,
with R = {r
1
, r
2
, . . . , r
|R|
}. In this case, let b
R
de-
note a local effect. A global rule V can be spec-
ified by the input/output relation V
b
R
= b
0
R
0
.
However, in the extensive literature about classi-
cal cellular automata—see e.g. [59] for reference,
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 54
though we cannot even try to provide an exhaus-
tive account of the relevant bibliography—it is
customary to express V through its local rule,
which is specified by its action on local states.
The only point we want to discuss here is the
apparent clash of our general wrapping lemma
with results in the literature. In particular, in
Ref. [31] a counterexample to the classical ver-
sion of the wrapping lemma is provided, referring
to [48]. The local rule for the counterexample is
the following. Let G = Z
r
with r 6∈ 3Z. The rule
defined by
b
0
j
= b
j
r
1
b
j
b
j
r
1
(117)
What we claim here is that, according to our
notion of neighbourhood based on definition 36,
the above automaton has a neighbourhood sys-
tem where N
+
i
is actually much larger than
{j
r
1, j, j
r
1}. Indeed, if one considers the
action of V on the algebra of transformations in-
stead of its action on states, one can easily realise
that N
+
i
= G for every i. However, by checking
the conditions for no-signalling, it is easy to re-
alise that the rule in Eq. (117) only signals to
sites i 1, i, and i 1. Thus, while no-signalling
is necessary for no causal influence, the converse
is not true.
We remark that the definition of causal influ-
ence that we give, based on transformations, is
inspired by the quantum definition, which indeed
involves the generators of the local algebra, and
thus the Kraus representatives of transformations
rather than the mere set of local states. In this
respect, the notion of neighbourhood used in the
literature on CA is different from the quantum
one, and we point to this relevant difference as
the responsible for the apparent incompatibility
discussed in Ref. [31]. The subject was exten-
sively studied in Ref. [60] and later in Ref.[61],
where the authors maintain the notion of neigh-
bourhood for classical CA based on the signalling
condition, and prove a bound on the mismatch
between the classical neighbourhood of a given
CA and the neighbourhood of the quantum ver-
sion of the same CA.
9.2 Quantum case
Quantum cellular automata represent now a
widely studied field of research. After the very
general analysis of Refs. [31, 32, 33, 61], there are
various results in the literature about quantum
cellular automata. Here we cite the very general
classification of Ref. [62, 63], while for extensive
reviews we refer to Refs. [64, 65].
9.3 Fermionic case
For the presentation of fermionic theory as an
OPT we refer to [36, 37]. The Fermionic systems
are fully specified by the algebra A generated by
local field operators ψ
i
. In fact, A is the alge-
bra of field operator polynomials. This algebra is
Z
2
-graded, with two modules A
E
and A
O
, given
by the span of even and odd polynomials, respec-
tively. No combination of even and odd poly-
nomials is allowed. As in all quantum theories,
A provides a simplified representation in terms
of Kraus operators of the algebra of transforma-
tions, which is not graded, but rather reducible
to a direct sum. Linear combinations of transfor-
mations indeed do not correspond to linear com-
binations of the corresponding Kraus operators.
The local systems for a site g of a cellular au-
tomaton in this case are registers made of one
or more local Fermionic modes. Local field op-
erators are then labelled ψ
i,g
, where g G and
i J
g
= {1, . . . , n
g
}, |J
g
| representing the size
of the register at site g. Since the local algebra
A
g
is finitely generated, the locality requirement
implies that V is given by a local rule, which in
turn is completely specified by its action on the
local generators ψ
i,g
for every g G. Thus, one
has
V (ψ
i,f
)
=
X
g(N
+
f
)
×k
jJ
g
s,t∈{0,1}
T
(g,j,s,t)
i,f
ψ
s
j
1
j
1
,g
1
ψ
t
j
1
j
1
,g
1
. . . ψ
s
k
j
k
,g
k
ψ
t
i
k
j
k
,g
k
,
where J
g
:
=
×
gN
+
f
J
g
. Most of the automata
studied so far in the literature are linear, namely
V (ψ
i,f
) =
X
gN
+
f
jJ
g
T
j,g
0
i,f
ψ
j,g
.
Remarkable exceptions are represented by
Refs. [44, 66, 45]. In particular, in Ref. [45] the
full classification of Fermionic cellular automata
with |J
g
| = 1 on Cayley graphs of Z
2
× Z
2
and Z
was carried out.
As regards Fermionic cellular automata, we
would like to remark that, despite Fermionic
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 55
theory being of type 2, they satisfy the wrap-
ping lemma in the form of lemma 68, instead of
lemma 69. This is due to the fact that Fermionic
transofrmations, like quantum transformations,
admit a Kraus decomposition, and can thus be
represented through Kraus operators instead of
completely positive maps. It turns out that local
Fermionic field operators ψ
j,g
and ψ
j,g
provide a
basis for the full algebra of Fermionic operators.
Thus, in the Fermionic case, if Eq. (110) is sat-
isfied for local transformations, it is always sat-
isfied. Real quantum theory, which shares many
features with Fermionic theory, is different in this
respect, and we conjecture that a counterexam-
ple to the thesis of lemma 68 can be found in the
latter case.
10 Conclusion
Summarising the content of the manuscript, we
defined the composition of denumerably many
systems from an OPT, starting from the space of
quasi-local effects, and defining quasi-local trans-
formations. We then define states of such system
in terms of suitable functionals on the space of
effects. Among these, there are some that can
be interpreted as the result of local preparations,
and that we deem quasi-local states.
We defined global update rules for finite or in-
finite systems, and proved a generalisation of a
block-decomposition theorem for GURs. We then
analysed those GURs that are homogeneous. The
definition of homogeneity is a big chapter on its
own, and deserves a careful treatment. As a con-
sequence of the definition, we proved that for ho-
mogenous GURs the memory array is organised
as the Cayley graph of a group. We then defined
locality for GURs, and studied its consequences
in detail.
In the last section we used homogeneity and lo-
cality to define cellular automata, and proved the
wrapping lemma under very general assumptions.
The theory developed here is of fundamental
importance for an approach to physical laws as
information-processing algorithms, and will be
used for the construction of statistical mechanics
in post-quantum theories, as well as the recon-
struction of dynamical laws in space-time beyond
the now established approach based on quantum
walks, thus encompassing interacting quantum
and post-quantum field theories.
Acknowledgments
This publication was made possible through the
support of a grant from the John Templeton
Foundation under the project ID#60609 Causal
Quantum Structures. The opinions expressed
in this publication are those of the authors and
do not necessarily reflect the views of the John
Templeton Foundation. The author wishes to
thank G. M. D’Ariano, A. Bisio, A. Tosini, and
F. Buscemi for many inspiring discussions. Sug-
gestions about the terminology by G. Chiribella
are also acknowledged that were useful to sharpen
the notion that is now defined as causal influence.
A particular thank to J. Barrett for fruitful con-
versations about various facets of causal influence
and signalling, and to M. Erba for his help in tun-
ing the definitions and dissipating misconceptions
on the same subject.
A Identification of the sup- and oper-
ational norm for effects
We show that, under the hypothesis of assump-
tion (16), one has kak
op
= kak
sup
for every
a [[
¯
A]]
R
. Indeed, if [[
¯
A]]
+
= [[A]]
+
, then, by
theorem 5, one has
[[
¯
A]] = {a [[
¯
A]]
R
| 0 (a|ρ), (e a|ρ), ρ [[A]]}.
(118)
First of all, one can rephrase the above condition
as
[[
¯
A]] = {a [[
¯
A]]
R
| 0 (a|ρ), (e a|ρ), ρ [[A]]
1
}.
(119)
Indeed, since [[A]]
1
[[A]], the set on the l.h.s. in
Eq. (118) is clearly a subset of that on the l.h.s. in
Eq. (119). Moreover, since every state ρ [[A]]
is proportional by a constant κ [0, 1] to a
deterministic one ρ
0
[[A]]
1
(see remark 1), if
0 (a|σ), (e a|σ) for all σ [[A]]
1
, then
0 (a|ρ), (e a|ρ) for all ρ [[A]]. Then, by
the identity in Eq. (119), one can identify the set
[[
¯
A]] as the subset of [[
¯
A]]
R
containing only those
functionals a on [[A]]
R
such that 0 (a|ρ) and
0 1 (a|ρ) for ρ [[A]]
1
, and, in turn, the
above condition is equivalent to
[[
¯
A]] = {a [[
¯
A]]
R
| 0 (a|ρ) 1, ρ [[A]]}.
Now, we remind that λ J(a) if and only if
λe ± a 0. Under our hypotheses, this means
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 56
that λ ± (a|ρ) 0 for every ρ [[A]]. Thus,
|(a|ρ)| λ for every ρ [[A]]. Finally, we can con-
clude that kak
op
kak
sup
. On the other hand, if
kak
op
< kak
sup
, then there exists ε > 0 such that
for every ρ [[A]] one has |(a|ρ)| kak
sup
ε.
In particular, this is true for ρ
1
[[A]]
1
. Conse-
quently
|(a|ρ)| = κ|(a|ρ
1
)| κ(kak
sup
ε) ρ [[A]],
where 0 κ 1 and ρ = κρ
1
. Then (e|ρ) = κ,
and
({kak
sup
ε}e ± a|ρ) 0, ρ [[A]].
Finally, this implies that kak
sup
ε J(a), which
is absurd. Then, kak
sup
= kak
op
.
B Quasi-local states
We start considering arbitrary finite disjoint par-
titions of the system A
G
. Let B
:
= {B
i
}
i=1
de-
note a disjoint partition of the set G into finite
blocks, i.e. 0 < |B
i
| < for every i N. The
set of such partitions (quotiented by the irrele-
vant ordering of regions) is denoted by B.
Definition 51. For a given partition B B, we
define the set of finite B-regions of G as
R
(G,B)
:
=
R G | R =
k
[
j=1
B
i
j
; 0 k <
,
(120)
and the set of B-regions of G as
R
(G,B)
:
=
R G | R =
k
[
j=1
B
i
j
; 0 k
,
(121)
where for k = 0 we define
0
[
j=1
B
i
j
:
= .
Given R =
S
k
j=1
B
i
j
in R
(G,B)
, let N
(B)
R
:
=
{i
j
}
k
j=1
.
Remark 10. Clearly, R
(G,B)
R
(G,B)
. It is also
trivial to prove that R
(G,B)
and R
(G,B)
are closed
under , , \.
Given a finite region R R
(G)
, for any parti-
tion B B it is possible to cover R with regions
of B.
Definition 52. Given B B, the cover in B of
a region R G, denoted B(R), is the minimal
B-region C =
S
k
j=1
B
i
j
such that R C.
The above notion of cover is well defined, as
proved by the following lemma.
Lemma 70. Let R G. The cover B(R) in B
of R exists and is unique.
Proof. First of all, the set of B-regions S
R
(G,B)
such that R S is not empty, since
R G R
(G,B)
. We just need to prove that,
having defined C(R, B)
:
= {S R
(G,B)
| R S},
there is always a unique minimal element B(R)
C(R, B), i.e. such that no B-region strictly con-
tained in B(R) covers R. As to existence, let
h R. Then h B
l
h
for some l
h
. One can eas-
ily realise that R C
:
=
S
hR
B
l
h
. Moreover,
if we remove a given B-region B
l
h
from C, and
h B
l
h
, then h 6∈ C \ B
l
h
, thus C is a minimal
cover of R in B. As to uniqueness, suppose that
there are two different minimal covers of R in B,
say C
1
and C
2
. In this case, it is not restrictive
to suppose that there is h G such that h C
1
and h 6∈ C
2
. Let B
i
B be the set such that
h B
i
. One has B
i
C
1
and B
i
C
2
= . Since
R C
2
, we can conclude that R B
i
= , and
thus R (C
1
\ B
i
) C(R, B). Thus, C
1
cannot
be minimal in C(R, B).
The cover B(R) can also be thought of as the
intersection of all covers of R in B.
Lemma 71. The cover B(R) of a finite region
R is finite.
Proof. Every element g
k
R belongs to some
B
i
k
B, where k 7→ i
k
is generally not injec-
tive. It is then clear that R
S
|R|
k=1
B
i
k
, and
thus B(R)
S
|R|
k=1
B
i
k
.
Given one partition B B, we can now define
the set of states that differ on finitely many blocks
from a given assignment of states of blocks in B.
First, we define the reference state as follows.
Definition 53 (Reference local state). Given a
partition B B, a reference local state over B is
a map
ρ
0
: N
G
jN
[[A
B
j
]]
1
:: j 7→ ρ
0j
[[A
B
j
]]
1
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 57
A reference local state allows one to attribute a
state to any finite region R R
(G)
by the follow-
ing procedure. First, let us consider the B-cover
B(R) of R. Then, the state of B(R) is given by
ρ
0
[B(R)]
:
=
O
i
j
N
(B)
B(R)
ρ
0i
j
.
Finally, we discard all the extra systems in the
region B(R) \ R.
ρ
0|R
:
= ρ
0
[B(R)]
|R
.
The above construction is then formalised in
the following definition.
Definition 54. The state of a finite region R
R
(G,B)
in the reference local state ρ
0
is defined as
ρ
0|R
R
:
=
ρ
0
[B(R)]
R
B(R)\R
e
,
ρ
0|∅
:
= 1.
Given a partition B and a reference local state
ρ
0
, let us now define the set of primitive local
states as follows.
Definition 55. The set of primitive local states
is
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
:
= {(σ, R) | σ [[A
R
]]
R
; R R
(G,B)
}.
This set collects all the generalised local prepa-
rations of finite regions of B. As in the case
of effects, we introduce the simplified notation
σ
S
:
= (σ, S). A choice of reference local state
ρ
0
, allows us to interpret a given element σ
S
of
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
as a preparation of the region S in
the state σ. Thus, the element σ
S
allows one to
attribute a generalised state τ [[A
T
]]
R
to any
region T R
(G)
as follows (see fig. 3)
τ
:
= σ
|ST
ρ
0|(T \S)
. (122)
Definition 56. Given a reference local state ρ
0
over B we define the following equivalence rela-
tion in Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
σ
S
ρ
0
τ
T
(
σ = ν ρ
0|(S\T )
,
τ = ν ρ
0|(T \S)
,
(123)
for some ν [[A
ST
]]
R
.
01
<latexit sha1_base64="wcn3oa0+0vL9+3GXSv1gdPQl2qo=">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</latexit>
02
<latexit sha1_base64="k9GxzKcL0UbtRm+kbfu6qag/vDA=">AAAIVXicdZVpb9s2GMfVY42bHT32sm/YqQU6IDAsJz0GBEFjxzmaHj4TO2UQUBTlCDpD0kUMVZ9ib7fPNezDDBglkmK9tQIM6/k9/+fgI5FysyhgvNX6+8bNW7e/u7PWuLv+/Q8//nTv/oOHJyxdUEwmOI1SOnURI1GQkAkPeESmGSUodiNy6obd0n/6iVAWpMmYLzNyHqN5EvgBRlygGaSX6UXeahcX9+1Wc7P9/JWzCeTNiy158/K3LeA0W9VlW+rqXzxYewG9FC9iknAcIcY+Oq2Mn+eI8gBHpFiHC0YyhEM0J3nVZwGeCuQBP6Xil3BQ0RUdilmM+OWG+GfL2N1gPEZ0Sb0NNxbRpYut6EtCmc+Kr2X5WsTHBfdfnedBki04SbBsyV9EgKegHA/wAkowj5biBmEaiLUAfIkowlwMcaXKnKLsMsDXxfrTlZaWHqkaqmqA6yWA18s0K6edoyjSDqEb4IDiRcAFEiGQZdh28hxWPfvAdgrtOMxLJzhUdp+mqS90xGNhkMEMUZikQeKJB5FD1weVvwl0+BXx8idwA7qR6JBdLRAlT8qgAkh/N86ia1nWdUFXRe3kkKJkXj3I0t7OYSTtygzDHO7AxwDuSNt1c7gNH8PtAlQ2pwnzaSwWJNeDabmgyhUl/3HSuPTJOLorJiDAbiHFtCPtjl4N7UrQ1YI9ae8Vej20J0mv0Dn3Jdg3kgNJDmrJkQRHdRksAdZlBtIemBxDSYZ1jpEEIyOZSjKtJTMJZkZyJslZTfhurqcnpiBRx6COapB3Desq2Z5Be3W6kYEjpTsw6ECne2vYWyV7b9B7LTs27Fg/6iPDjrRubNhYpZsYNKm7OzHwROlODTrV6d4Z9k7JpgZNtWxm2EzJzgw607J9w8RLIdkHwz5oXc+wnl7smy9i32jh0MChytc3qA+Kbz+LlUHpHZlwRnh9FOQ93y/q92O06htx4xqLRF/6xmIHszJUlR+YWgPF5jSrDh03jbzyxE2jvDx41GpHGUpMJWHoVCEXUZ9tR2x/IKUuLbfztu18VhIvVJIw1BrPLTWua0THUvOrVnSE/cy4R13bsdsVsdu1aEzlnhnT+oTEqBJW9e226er/0h5HJckP1cYWA6sGsHLiDgmKWF6fiUPN3U9EntGuL8eksBhS6QKJBqECoQZXClwV6+JLqz+n4Ns3J+2ms9lsD7bs1x31zW1Yj6xfrGeWY720XluHVt+aWNiKrd+tP6w/1/5a+6dxu3FHSm/eUDE/WytX496/uWTtag==</latexit>
03
<latexit sha1_base64="sOt3vdlSUKaja88vDY1pstla2yI=">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</latexit>
04
<latexit sha1_base64="8fgSTMNFQ5aFUElE9FFZ5gEyCq8=">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</latexit>
05
<latexit sha1_base64="Y9xd9Uckk+Cc5XSv5JJJMayGtjU=">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</latexit>
06
<latexit sha1_base64="AUdkV9uV3TzC83+guFueH3YQvEQ=">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</latexit>
07
<latexit sha1_base64="nLKtHiRE5+IoXsYlmAr3AuR3yRM=">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</latexit>
08
<latexit sha1_base64="wxVEbPaVRzCK3XoX3MzVgBUPV88=">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</latexit>
09
<latexit sha1_base64="VlqwQbJd7gn9CLhEDH5wkqDeAMQ=">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</latexit>
010
<latexit sha1_base64="77XfSYRmbYpF2Wa0MwevPeH7A6U=">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</latexit>
011
<latexit sha1_base64="bXSZkKN7UVRmN000ftK0y9OLlN4=">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</latexit>
B
1
<latexit sha1_base64="hdKGxyj9oDmC260d3KDDH1MX91I=">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</latexit>
B
2
<latexit sha1_base64="8qsTOhWtMQtOc9jpAnYSPQY4QlI=">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</latexit>
B
3
<latexit sha1_base64="SIpjGbzmQ5IqgvG0T7gt7KKi62s=">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</latexit>
B
4
<latexit sha1_base64="XP22PJKjUEYCvUGjoSpDqqYu4/8=">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</latexit>
B
6
<latexit sha1_base64="F52eIMer2sqAg/q+q5s5nLcz5CM=">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</latexit>
B
7
<latexit sha1_base64="JsTve11eOpOlVqJUbbyX9n1imGM=">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</latexit>
B
5
<latexit sha1_base64="HFQ7qoI3zoCEIz93EtDN3ZOSEoQ=">AAAIT3icdZVbb9s2FMfV7uI0u7TdHvfCTi3QAYFhOellQBA0dpxL04tt2YmTKghIinIEXUPSRQxVH2Gv2+fa4z7J3oZRIinWWysgCM/v/M+FRyaF8jhkvNP569btL7786uvW2p31b7797vu79+7/cMKyBcVkirM4ozMEGYnDlEx5yGMyyymBCYrJKYr6lf/0PaEszNIJX+bkIoHzNAxCDLlAbu/yyeU9u9Pe7D557mwCuXi6JRfPft0CTrtTP7alnuHl/dZTz8/wIiEpxzFk7J3TyflFASkPcUzKdW/BSA5xBOekqDsswSOBfBBkVPylHNR0RQcTlkB+tSH+s2WCNhhPIF1SfwMlIrpysRV9RSgLWPmpLJ+KeLfgwfOLIkzzBScpli0FixjwDFSDAX5ICebxUiwgpqHYC8BXkELMxfhWqswpzK9CfFOuP1ppaemTuqG6BrhZAu9mmeXVnAsYx9ohdCMcUrwIuUAixGM5tp2i8OqeA2A7pXYcFpUTHCp7SLMsEDrisyjMvRxSL83C1BcvovBQAGp/G+jwa+IXD70ND8WiQ3a9gJQ8rIJKIP39JI9vZFmEQF9F7RQehem8fpGVvV14sbRrM4oKb8d7ALwdaSNUeNveA2+7BLXNacoCmogNyf1gWm2odsXpf5w0qXwyju6KCQiwW0ox7Um7p3dD+xL0tWBP2nul3g8dSDIodc59CfaN5ECSg0ZyJMFRUwZLgHWZkbRHJsdYknGTw5XANZKZJLNGcibBmZGcS3LeEL5b6OmJKUjUM6inGuR9w/pKtmfQXpPONdBVugODDnS6V4a9UrI3Br3RsmPDjvWrPjLsSOsmhk1UuqlB06a7EwNPlO7UoFOd7rVhr5VsZtBMy84MO1Oyc4POtWzfMPGjkOytYW+1bmDYQG/25UexL7VwbOBY5RsaNATl59/FyqD0iUw5I7y5CopBEJTN78Nd9bncuCYi0ce+iTjBrApV5Uem1kixOc3rSwdlsV/duFlcVBeP2q2bw9RUEoZOFXER9cF2xPEHUopodZy3beeDkviRkkSR1vio0iBkRMdS84tW9IT92Ljdvu3Y3ZrY3UY0ofLMTGhzQ2JYC+v6dtd09X/pgMOKFIfqYIuB1QNYuXHHBMasaO7EseboPZF3NArkmBQWQ6pcINUgUiDS4FqB63JdfGn15xR8fnHSbTub7e5oy37RU9/cNesn62frseVYz6wX1qE1tKYWtubWb9bv1h+tP1t/t/5ZU9Lbt9TiR2vlWbvzL8Qc66U=</latexit>
B
8
<latexit sha1_base64="AITtDnWY5win6ADXYCn+no7s/SI=">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</latexit>
B
9
<latexit sha1_base64="EHz8/ZD8efb6gB9Bjm2rtAsr+04=">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</latexit>
B
10
<latexit sha1_base64="nDcI0ZVtEf7oDYQW1ImFHs1Z+xk=">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</latexit>
B
11
<latexit sha1_base64="PQTCtEc5gl3MZGPmAS3MwWZwtJo=">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</latexit>
(a)
01
<latexit sha1_base64="wcn3oa0+0vL9+3GXSv1gdPQl2qo=">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</latexit>
02
<latexit sha1_base64="k9GxzKcL0UbtRm+kbfu6qag/vDA=">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</latexit>
03
<latexit sha1_base64="sOt3vdlSUKaja88vDY1pstla2yI=">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</latexit>
06
<latexit sha1_base64="AUdkV9uV3TzC83+guFueH3YQvEQ=">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</latexit>
09
<latexit sha1_base64="VlqwQbJd7gn9CLhEDH5wkqDeAMQ=">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</latexit>
010
<latexit sha1_base64="77XfSYRmbYpF2Wa0MwevPeH7A6U=">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</latexit>
011
<latexit sha1_base64="bXSZkKN7UVRmN000ftK0y9OLlN4=">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</latexit>
B
1
<latexit sha1_base64="hdKGxyj9oDmC260d3KDDH1MX91I=">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</latexit>
B
2
<latexit sha1_base64="8qsTOhWtMQtOc9jpAnYSPQY4QlI=">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</latexit>
B
3
<latexit sha1_base64="SIpjGbzmQ5IqgvG0T7gt7KKi62s=">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</latexit>
B
6
<latexit sha1_base64="F52eIMer2sqAg/q+q5s5nLcz5CM=">AAAIT3icdZVbb9s2FMfV7uI0u7Xb417YqQU6IDAsJ0s7IAgaO86l6cW27MRJFQQkRTmCriHpIoaqj7DX7XPtcZ9kb8MokRTrrRUQhOd3/ufCI5NCeRwy3un8defuZ59/8WVr7d76V19/8+139x98f8qyBcVkirM4ozMEGYnDlEx5yGMyyymBCYrJGYr6lf/sHaEszNIJX+bkMoHzNAxCDLlAbu9q++q+3Wlvdn955mwCudjekounv24Bp92pH9tSz/DqQWvb8zO8SEjKcQwZe+t0cn5ZQMpDHJNy3VswkkMcwTkp6g5L8FggHwQZFX8pBzVd0cGEJZBfb4j/bJmgDcYTSJfU30CJiK5cbEVfEcoCVn4sy8ci3i548OyyCNN8wUmKZUvBIgY8A9VggB9Sgnm8FAuIaSj2AvA1pBBzMb6VKnMK8+sQ35brj1daWvqkbqiuAW6XwLtdZnk15wLGsXYI3QiHFC9CLpAI8ViObacovLrnANhOqR1HReUER8oe0iwLhI74LApzL4fUS7Mw9cWLKDwUgNrfBjr8hvjFI2/DQ7HokN0sICWPqqASSH8/yeNbWRYh0FdRu4VHYTqvX2Rl7xReLO3ajKLC2/UeAm9X2ggV3o730NspQW1zmrKAJmJDcj+YVhuqXXH6HydNKp+Mo3tiAgLslVJMe9Lu6d3QvgR9LdiX9n6p90MHkgxKnfNAggMjOZTksJEcS3DclMESYF1mJO2RyTGWZNzkcCVwjWQmyayRnEtwbiQXklw0hO8VenpiChL1DOqpBnnfsL6S7Ru036RzDXSV7tCgQ53upWEvley1Qa+17MSwE/2qjw071rqJYROVbmrQtOnu1MBTpTsz6Eyne2XYKyWbGTTTsnPDzpXswqALLTswTPwoJHtj2ButGxg20Jt98UHsCy0cGzhW+YYGDUH56XexMih9IlPOCG+ugmIQBGXz+3BXfS43rolI9KFvIk4wq0JV+ZGpNVJsTvP60kFZ7Fc3bhYX1cWjduvmMDWVhKFTRVxEvbcdcfyBlCJaHecd23mvJH6kJFGkNT6qNAgZ0YnU/KwVPWE/MW63bzt2tyZ2txFNqDwzE9rckBjWwrq+3TVd/V864LAixZE62GJg9QBWbtwxgTErmjtxrDl6R+QdjQI5JoXFkCoXSDWIFIg0uFHgplwXX1r9OQWfXpx2285muzvasp/31Dd3zfrR+sl6YjnWU+u5dWQNramFrbn1m/W79Ufrz9bfrX/WlPTuHbX4wVp51u79C8wF66Y=</latexit>
B
9
<latexit sha1_base64="EHz8/ZD8efb6gB9Bjm2rtAsr+04=">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</latexit>
B
10
<latexit sha1_base64="nDcI0ZVtEf7oDYQW1ImFHs1Z+xk=">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</latexit>
B
11
<latexit sha1_base64="PQTCtEc5gl3MZGPmAS3MwWZwtJo=">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</latexit>
B
4
[ B
5
[ B
7
[ B
8
<latexit sha1_base64="q4lKlrzL+Lphpfv8tS7QmIl6Y54=">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</latexit>
<latexit sha1_base64="uKDlDNW/9c6Gk5Ygv9nR1Js3ZMA=">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</latexit>
(b)
Figure 3: An illustrative example of a reference local
state ρ
0
(a) for a partition of a finite set G into 11
regions, along with a primitive local state σ
R
(b) with
R = B
4
B
5
B
7
B
8
. The dots represent the elements
of G.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 58
The symbol σ
Sρ
0
will denote the equivalence
class of σ
S
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
under the relation
ρ
0
.
Notice that in Eq. (123), thanks to closure of
R
(G,B)
under set difference, one has (S \ T ), (T \
S) R
(G,B)
, and thus the definition of the equiva-
lence relation
ρ
0
involves exclusively B-regions.
Moreover, all the regions involved in the defini-
tion are finite.
Lemma 72. Let σ
S
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
. Then for
every R R
(G,B)
such that RS = one has (σ
ρ
0|R
)
SR
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
and (σ ρ
0|R
)
SR
ρ
0
σ
S
.
Proof. First of all, as R
(G,B)
is closed under
union, clearly S R R
(G,B)
, and thus (σ
ρ
0|R
)
SR
Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
. Now, S (S R) = S,
and thus the condition in Eq. (123) is satisfied
for T = S R, T \ S = R, S T = S, ν = σ,
ρ
0|(T \S)
= ρ
0|R
, and ρ
0|(S\T )
= 1.
We now provide a way to identify a canonical
representative of the equivalence class σ
0
de-
fined as follows.
Definition 57. The minimal representative ˜σ
R
σ
of the equivalence class σ
0
is defined through
R
σ
:
=
\
SR
(σ,R)
S, ˜σ
R
σ
ρ
0
σ
R
, (124)
where
R
(σ,R)
:
= {S R
(G,B)
| τ [[A
S
]]
R
: τ
S
ρ
0
σ
R
}.
Lemma 73. The minimal representative exists
and is unique.
For the proof, see the analogous lemma 9.
Definition 58. The set of generalised local
states over B upon ρ
0
is
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
:
= Pre[[A
G
]]
(B)
R
/
ρ
0
. (125)
Its elements will be denoted by symbols like ρ
Sρ
0
.
We now define linear combinations of local
states.
Definition 59. Let σ
Sρ
0
, τ
T ρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
, and
a R. Then we have
a(σ
Sρ
0
)
:
=
(
()
Sρ
0
a 6= 0
0
ρ
0
a = 0,
σ
Sρ
0
+ τ
T ρ
0
:
= ν
ST ρ
0
,
ν
:
= σ ρ
0|(T \S)
+ ρ
0|(S\T )
τ.
We will denote by R
σ+τ
the region where the
minimal representative of the class σ
Sρ
0
+ τ
T ρ
0
differs from ρ
0
. As in the case of effects, it is not
always true that R
σ+τ
= R
σ
R
τ
. As an example,
consider σ = α
i
1
β
i
2
and τ = α
i
1
(ρ
0i
2
β
i
2
),
with α
i
1
6= ρ
0i
1
, β
i
2
6= ρ
0i
2
, and R
σ
= R
τ
=
B
i
1
B
i
2
. Then σ + τ = α
i
1
ρ
0i
2
, and clearly
R
σ+τ
= B
i
1
, which is strictly included in R
σ
=
R
τ
= R
σ
R
τ
.
Definition 60. The set of local states over B
upon ρ
0
is
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L
:
= {σ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
| σ [[A
S
]]}.
An element σ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
is a local state over
B upon ρ
0
. A subset of special interest is that of
deterministic local states over B upon ρ
0
, defined
as
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L1
:
= {σ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L
| σ [[A
S
]]
1
}.
We now characterise the vector space of gener-
alised states as follows.
Lemma 74. The set of generalized local states
in B upon ρ
0
equipped with the operations defined
in Def. 59 is a real vector space. It is the space
of finite real combinations of deterministic local
states in B upon the same state ρ
0
:
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
= Span
R
([[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L1
), (126)
The proof is trivial and we omit it.
We now show that quasi-local states are
bounded linear functionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. We start
considering the pairing of local states [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
with local effects [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
, defined as follows.
Definition 61. Every σ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
ρ
0
LR
iden-
tifies a functional on [[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
as follows. For
a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
let
(a
R
|σ
Sρ
0
)
:
=
σ
|RS
RS
a
ρ
0|R\S
R\S
. (127)
We now prove that the above pairing is well-
defined, namely it does not depend on the repre-
sentative in the class σ
Sρ
0
, nor on the representa-
tive in the class a
R
. This is done in the next two
lemmas.
Lemma 75. For every a
R
[[
¯
A
G
]]
LR
the result
of Eq. (127) is independent of the choice of rep-
resentative τ
T ρ
0
in the class σ
Sρ
0
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 59
Proof. By hypothesis, there exists ν [[A
ST
]]
R
such that
σ = ν ρ
0S\T
, τ = ν ρ
0T \S
.
Then we have
(a
R
|σ
Sρ
0
) =(a|ν
|(ST )R
ρ
0|[(S\T )R](R\S)
)
(a
R
|τ
T ρ
0
) =(a|ν
|(ST )R
ρ
0|[(T \S)R](R\T )
).
A straightforward set-theoretic calculation gives
that [(S\T )R](R\S) = [(T \S)R](R\T ) =
R \ (S T ), and thus (a
R
|σ
Sρ
0
) = (a
R
|τ
T ρ
0
).
On similar lines, we have the following result.
Lemma 76. For every partition B B, every
reference local state ρ
0
over B, and every local
state τ
T ρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
, the result of Eq. (127) is
independent of the choice of representative b
S
in
the class a
R
.
Proof. If ˜c
R
c
is the minimal representative of
a
R
= b
S
, by Eq. (10), one has
a = ˜c e
R\R
c
,
b = ˜c e
S\R
c
.
Now, by the defining equation 127, we have that
(a
R
|τ
T ρ
0
) = (a|τ
|RT
ρ
0|(R\T )
)
=(˜c e
R\R
c
|τ
|RT
ρ
0|(R\T )
)
=(˜c|τ
|R
c
T
ρ
0|R
c
\T
),
and similarly we obtain
(b
S
|τ
T ρ
0
) = (˜c|τ
|R
c
T
ρ
0|(R
c
\T )
).
The above results give us a hint that for ev-
ery B B and every ρ
0
, the space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
is a
submanifold of the space [[A
G
]]
R
. We now com-
plete the real vector spaces [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
to Banach
spaces. For this purpose, we start equipping all
spaces [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
with a norm.
Definition 62. Given an element σ of the space
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
, its norm is defined as
kσk
B
0
:
= k˜σk
op
, (128)
where k·k
op
denotes the operational norm on
[[A
R
σ
]]
R
.
Lemma 77. Given an element σ of [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
,
for τ
T
in the corresponding equivalence class, one
has
kσk
B
0
= kτk
op
,
where k·k
op
denotes the operational norm on
[[A
T
]]
R
.
Proof. By definition of the relation
ρ
0
, and of
minimal representative ˜σ
R
σ
of σ, one has
τ = ˜σ ρ
0(T \R
σ
)
.
Thus, kτ k
op
= k˜σ ρ
0(T \R
σ
)
k
op
. Now, by
lemma 3
kτk
op
= k˜σk
op
= kσk
B
0
.
We can now show that vectors in [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
are
bounded linear functionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
.
Definition 63. Let a = [a
n
R
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and
ρ = ρ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
ρ
0
LR
. We define
(a|ρ)
:
= lim
n→∞
(a
n
R
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
). (129)
With this definition, we can now prove that lo-
cal states are actually bounded linear functionals
on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
.
Lemma 78. For a = [a
n
R
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and
ρ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
ρ
0
LR
, one has
|(a|ρ)| kak
sup
kρk
B
0
. (130)
Proof. We start considering the case of a local
effect a
R
. In this case, us define
a
0
:
= (2kak
sup
)
1
(kak
sup
e
R
+ a) 0,
a
1
:
= (2kak
sup
)
1
(kak
sup
e
R
a) 0,
a
0
+ a
1
= e
R
, kak
sup
(a
0
a
1
) = a,
we have that
|(a
R
|ρ
Sρ
0
)| = |(a
R
|ρ
|RS
ρ
0|R\S
)|
= kak
sup
|({¯a
0
¯a
1
} e
S\R
|ρ ρ
0|R\S
)|
kak
sup
kρ
Sρ
0
k
B
0
,
where a
i
|
:
= (a
i
|I
RS
|ρ
0|R\S
). Let now a =
[a
n
R
n
]. Then we have
|(a
n
R
n
a
m
R
m
|ρ
Sρ
0
)|
ka
n
R
n
a
m
R
m
k
sup
kρ
Sρ
0
k
B
0
,
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 60
and thus actually (a
n
R
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
) is a Cauchy se-
quence. Finally, since for every n N one has
|(a
n
R
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
)| ka
n
k
sup
kρ
S
k
B
0
,
taking the limit for n on both sides we have
that
|(a|ρ
Sρ
0
)| kak
sup
kρ
Sρ
0
k
B
0
.
We now show that the definition in Eq. (129)
is independent of the sequence a
n
R
n
in the class
of a.
Lemma 79. Let a = [a
n
R
n
] = [b
n
R
0
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
,
and ρ
Sρ
0
[[A
G
]]
ρ
0
LR
. Then
lim
n→∞
(a
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
) = lim
n→∞
(b
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
). (131)
Proof. Remind that by definition, for every ε
there exists n
0
such that for n n
0
, it is
ka
n
R
n
b
n
R
0
n
k
sup
ε. Now, by lemma 78, this
implies that
|(a
n
R
n
b
n
R
0
n
|ρ
Sρ
0
)| εkρ
Sρ
0
k
B
0
,
and thus the thesis follows.
We finally close the vector space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
by
adding the limits of Cauchy sequences in the
norm k·k
B
0
, thus obtaining a Banach space
that we denote [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. We start considering
Cauchy sequences
σ : N [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
R
:: n 7→ σ
n
R
n
ρ
0
[[A
G
]]
ρ
0
LR
,
which make a real vector space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
CR
, con-
taining [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
as the subspace of constant
sequences. We then quotient [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
CR
by the
usual equivalence relation
=
, obtaining complete
normed real vector space.
Definition 64. The space of quasi-local states
in B upon ρ
0
is defined as the space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
:
=
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
CR
/
=
.
Inside the new Banach space that we defined,
we can single out a convex set of quasi-local
states, corresponding to preparations that can be
arbitrarily approximated by local protocols start-
ing from ρ
0
, along with the cone that they span,
and the convex set of deterministic states.
Definition 65. An element σ of [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
is a
quasi-local state if there exists σ
n
R
n
ρ
0
in the class
σ, and n
0
N, such that, for n n
0
, σ
n
R
n
ρ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L
. The set of quasi-local states in B upon
ρ
0
is denoted by [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
.
A quasi-local state σ in [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
is determinis-
tic, if there exists a sequence σ
n
R
n
in the class of
σ and n
0
N such that, for n n
0
, σ
n
R
n
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
L1
. The set of deterministic quasi-local
states is denoted by [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q1
.
We denote the subset of [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
of elements
σ = λρ, for λ 0 and ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
, as
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q+
. We will equivalently write σ 0 for
σ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q+
Analogously to the case of effects, the ele-
ments of [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
will be denoted by ρ =
[ρ
n
R
n
ρ
0
], with the convention that for a con-
stant Cauchy sequence ρ
n
R
n
ρ
0
= ρ
0
we will
set ρ
0
:
= [ρ
n
R
n
ρ
0
]. We define kρk
B
0
:
=
lim
n→∞
kρ
n
R
n
ρ
0
k
B
0
. One can straightforwardly
check that the space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
of quasi-local
states in B upon ρ
0
is a Banach space, the sets
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
and [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q1
are convex subsets, and
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q+
is a convex cone. The space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
can be identified with the dense submanifold con-
taining constant sequences σ
Sρ
0
.
For every partition B and every reference local
state ρ
0
, the Banach space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
is separa-
ble. Indeed, one can choose a basis in [[A
S
n
]]
R
for each region S
n
:
=
S
n
j=1
B
j
in the increasing
sequence {S
n
}
nN
of regions of B. Now, for ev-
ery ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
, and for every n N, given
the class ρ
n
R
n
ρ
0
defining ρ, one has R
n
S
m
for
sufficiently large m. Thus, linear combinations of
the countable collection of bases for S
m
are dense
in [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
.
We now show that actually, for every pair
(B, ρ
0
), the space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
is a subspace of
[[A
G
]]
R
, and k·k
k·k
B
0
on [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. First
of all, we extend the pairing of [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
and
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
to [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
and [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
.
Definition 66. Let a = [a
n
R
n
] [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
and
σ = [σ
n
S
n
ρ
0
] [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. Then we define
(a|σ)
:
= lim
n→∞
(a|σ
n
S
m
ρ
0
). (132)
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 61
The above definition is well-posed, as shown by
the following lemma, whose proof is a straightfor-
ward consequence of lemma 78.
Lemma 80. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and σ =
[σ
n
S
n
ρ
0
] = [σ
0
n
S
0
n
ρ
0
] [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
. Then
lim
n→∞
(a|σ
m
S
m
ρ
0
) = lim
n→∞
(a|σ
0
m
S
0
m
ρ
0
). (133)
Finally, we use the definition of sup-norm of ef-
fects to prove that vectors in the spaces [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
are bounded linear functionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. Also
in this case the proof follows straightforwardly
form lemma 78.
Lemma 81. Let a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
and ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
.
Then one has
|(a|ρ)| kak
sup
kρk
B
0
. (134)
Lemma 82. The spaces [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
are closed
subspaces of the extended space of states [[A
G
]]
R
.
On [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
it holds that k·k
B
0
k·k
.
Proof. We only need to prove that k·k
k·k
Q
,
since we already proved that [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
is a lin-
ear manifold in the space of bounded linear func-
tionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. First of all, by eq. (134)
one clearly has kρk
kρk
B
0
for all ρ
[[A
G
]]
QR
. For the converse, one can use the
same technique as for lemma 16, to prove that
kρk
B
0
kρk
for the case of a local state
ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
. Thus kρk
= kρk
B
0
for local
states ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
LR
. It is then straightforward
to conclude that equality holds for every quasi
local state ρ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
.
Notice that two partitions B and B
0
along with
two local reference states ρ
0
and ρ
0
0
might define
the same space [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
[[A
G
]]
(B
0
)
ρ
0
0
QR
. This is
the case if for every σ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
there exists a
state σ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B
0
)
ρ
0
0
QR
such that, σ = σ
0
, as func-
tionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. We then provide the following
definition.
Definition 67. We say that the two reference
local states (B, ρ
0
) and (B
0
, ρ
0
0
) are compatible,
and denote this relation by the symbol (B, ρ
0
)
(B
0
, ρ
0
0
), if for all σ [[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
there exists a
state σ
0
[[A
G
]]
(B
0
)
ρ
0
0
QR
such that, for every a
[[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, one has
(a|σ) = (a|σ
0
).
The equivalence classes of pairs (B, ρ
0
) under
the above relation will be denoted by [(B, ρ
0
)].
The norm k·k
B
0
can be extended to the space
of finite linear combinations of generalised quasi-
local states.
Definition 68. Let σ
i
[[A
G
]]
(B
(i)
)
ρ
(i)
0
QR
, for i =
1, . . . , k, with [(B
(i)
, ρ
(i)
0
)] 6= [(B
(j)
, ρ
(j)
0
)]. Then
we define
k
X
i=1
a
i
σ
i
Q
:
=
k
X
i=1
|a
i
|kσ
i
k
B
(i)
(i)
0
.
The space of finite sums as from definition 68
is a real vector subspace of [[A
G
]]
R
. Moreover,
as a real vector space, it is equipped with the
norm k·k
Q
. We can define the space of Cauchy
sequences in this space, and complete it by the
usual procedure. This leads us to the following
definition of the space of quasi-local states.
Definition 69. The space of generalised quasi-
local states of A
G
, denoted as [[A
G
]]
QR
, is
[[A
G
]]
QR
:
=
M
[B
0
]
[[A
G
]]
(B)
ρ
0
QR
,
where the direct sum denotes closure of the space
of finite linear combinations in the norm k·k
Q
.
The norm introduced above allows us to prove
that [[A
G
]]
QR
is a space of bounded linear func-
tionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, namely a subspace of [[A
G
]]
R
.
Lemma 83. Every quasi-local state ρ [[A
G
]]
QR
is a continuous functional on the space of quasi-
local effects a [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and
|(a|ρ)| kak
sup
kρk
Q
(135)
Proof. Let ρ [[A
G
]]
R
be a finite sum of the form
ρ =
k
X
i=1
a
i
σ
i
, σ
i
[[A
G
]]
(B
(i)
)
ρ
0
QR
. (136)
Then
(a|ρ)
:
=
k
X
i=1
a
i
(a|σ
i
). (137)
One can easily realise that |(a|ρ)| kak
sup
kρk
Q
.
Finally, by the above inequality, also the limit
of a Cauchy sequence in [[A
G
]]
QR
is a continuous
linear functional on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
, and satisfies
|(a|ρ)| kak
sup
kρk
Q
.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 62
We can now prove the following important re-
sult.
Lemma 84. The space [[A
G
]]
QR
is a closed sub-
space of the extended space of states [[A
G
]]
R
. On
[[A
G
]]
QR
it holds that k·k
Q
k·k
.
Proof. We only need to prove that k·k
k·k
Q
on finite sums of the form of eq. (136), since we
already proved that [[A
G
]]
QR
is obtained closing
a linear manifold in the space of bounded lin-
ear functionals on [[
¯
A
G
]]
QR
. The proof follows ex-
actly the same argument as for lemma 82, using
eq. (135) instead of eq. (134).
Notice that all local states allow us to de-
fine states of arbitrary finite regions S G, by
Eq. (122). We will now extend the definition of
local state for all quasi-local states in a fixed sec-
tor [[A]]
(B)
ρ
0
Q
, as follows. First, if ρ is quasi local,
then kρ
n
ρ
m
k
B
0
ε, and k(ρ
n
ρ
m
)|
S
k
op
kρ
n
ρ
m
k
B
0
ε. Thus, being the set of states
[[A
S
]] compact, ρ
S
:
= lim
n→∞
ρ
n
|
S
[[A
S
]].
The same is true for finte linear combinations,
as well as limits of Cauchy sequences thereof. In-
deed, given a finite combination of states ρ =
P
i
a
i
ρ
i
, one has
ρ
|S
:
=
X
i
a
i
ρ
i|S
[[A
S
]]
R
. (138)
Finally, if τ : N [[A]]
QR
, and kτ
n
τ
m
k
Q
ε,
then clearly k(τ
n
τ
m
)
|
S
k
op
ε, and thus
τ
|S
:
= lim
n→∞
(τ
n
)
|S
[[A
S
]]
R
. (139)
In view of the above considerations, we can now
define the set of states in [[A
G
]]
QR
.
Definition 70. The set [[A
G
]]
Q
of quasi-local
states is the (convex) set of generalised states ρ
for which, for every finite region S R
(G)
, the
restriction ρ
|S
of ρ to S is a state in [[A
S
]]. The
positive cone [[A
G
]]
Q+
of A
G
is
[[A
G
]]
Q+
:
= {σ [[A
G
]]
QR
| λ 0, ρ [[A
G
]]
Q
: σ = λρ}.
The set of deterministic quasi-local states of A
G
,
denoted as [[A
G
]]
Q1
, is
[[A
G
]]
Q1
:
= {ρ [[A
G
]]
Q
| (e
G
|ρ) = 1}.
Lemma 85. Definition 70 is compatible with def-
inition 16
Proof. We need to prove that the definition of
restriction to the finite region S provided in
Eq. (33) is equivalent to that of Eq. (139). We
start from the case of local states. In this case,
since effects are separating for states of finite
dimensional systems, one has (a
S
|ρ
T
) = (a
S
e
T \S
|ρ
|T
ρ
0|S\T
), and thus ρ
|S
= ρ
|(T S)
ρ
0|S\T
,
which is precisely the same as in Eq. (122). The
statement in the case of a general state ρ
[[A
G
]]
Q
is then straightforwardly proved, remind-
ing that |(a
S
|ρ ρ
n
)| ka
S
k
sup
kρ ρ
n
k
Q
.
Corollary 19. One has the following inclusions
[[A
G
]]
Q
[[A
G
]], [[A
G
]]
Q1
[[A
G
]]
1
. (140)
C Proof of identity 94
In order to keep the notation lighter, we do the
calculation for the case of C
=
I. The proof can
then be adapted to the general case by suitably
padding all transformations with I
C
and extend-
ing the region
˜
S to
˜
SC.
(V A V
1
I
H
1
)
a
˜
S
= W
1
(A I
H
1
)
W
a
˜
S
=W
1
(A I
H
1
)
S
N
+
S
N
+
S
S
0†
N
+
S
S
a
˜
S
=S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
S
N
+
S
N
+
S
R
(A I
H
1
)
× S
N
+
S
N
+
S
S
0†
N
+
S
S
a
˜
S
=S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
S
N
+
S
N
+
S
R
(A I
H
1
)
× S
N
+
S
N
+
S
R
S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
a
˜
S
=S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
S
R
(A I
H
1
)
S
R
S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
a
˜
S
=S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
(I
H
0
A )
S
0†
P
+
S
N
+
S
R
a
˜
S
=S
0†
R
(I
H
0
A )
S
0†
R
[a
˜
S
]
=S
0†
R
S
R
(A I
H
0
)
S
R
S
0†
R
[a
˜
S
],
where in the third identity we used Eq. (91), ob-
serving that (A I
H
1
)
S
N
+
S
N
+
S
S
0†
N
+
S
S
[a
˜
S
]
[[
¯
A
(G)
(N
+
S
R,0
(N
+
S
, 1)]]
QR
. In the fourth identity
we used the fact that a
˜
S
can be padded with e
X
to obtain an effect ˜a
X
on the region
˜
S X, and
then W
˜a
X
is an effect equivalent to W
a
S
. In
the fifth identity we used the fact that S
X
com-
mutes with Y
Y
I
H
1
for Y X = , and in
the seventh identity we used the fact that S
0
X
commutes with I
H
0
Y
Y
for Y X = .
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 63
D Homogeneity and causal influence
This section is devoted to the proof that, for π
Π
V
,
π(g) π(g
0
) g g
0
By definition, f f
0
if there exists R 3 f and
F [[A
(G)
f
C A
(G)
f
C]]
QR
,
(V I
C
)F (V
1
I
C
) 6∈ [[A
(G)
¯
f
0
C A
(G)
¯
f
0
C]]
QR
.
(141)
Let now f = π(g) for some π Π
V
. Now, by
homogeneity, and in particular by Eq. (104), one
has that F
0
[[A
(G)
π(g)
C A
(G)
π(g)
C]] if and only
if there exists F [[A
(G)
g
C A
(G)
g
C]] such that
F
0
= (T
π
I
C
)F (T
1
π
I
C
). Then one has
(V I
C
)F
0
(V
1
I
C
)
= (V T
π
I
C
)F (T
1
π
V
1
I
C
)
= (T
π
V I
C
)F (V
1
T
1
π
I
C
).
(142)
As a consequence, again by eq. (104), we have
that (V I
C
)F
0
(V
1
I
C
) [[A
(G)
¯
f
0
C
A
(G)
¯
f
0
C]], for f
0
= π(g
0
), if and only if (V
I
C
)F (V
1
I
C
) [[A
(G)
¯g
0
C A
(G)
¯g
0
C]]. Fi-
nally, comparing with Eq. (141), this implies that
π(g) π(g
0
) if and only if g g
0
.
E Proof of right and left invertibility of
a locally defined GUR
Here we prove right and left invertibility of V
defined starting from Eq. (109). First, notice that
ψ
P
R
S
0
N
R
P
R
\R
e
R
C
a
N
R
N
R
e
=
ψ
P
R
S
0
N
R
P
R
\R
e
R R
e
C
A
C
e
N
R
N
R
e
=
ψ
P
R
S
0
N
R
P
R
\R
S
0
N
R
P
R
e
R R
C
A
C
e
N
R
N
R
N
R
e
=
ψ
P
R
e
C
A
0
C
e
N
R
N
R
e
,
where we used Eq. (94).
Let us now define W by W
b
SC
:
= {(W
S
I
C
)b}
N
+
S
C
, where
N
+
S
W
S
S
:
=
N
+
S
S
0
S
N
+
S
e
η
S S
.
(143)
Then one can calculate W
V
a
RC
by the follow-
ing diagram
P
R
\R
S
0
N
R
P
R
e
ψ
P
R
S
0
N
R
P
R
\R
e
R R
a
C
η
N
R
N
R
N
R
e
=
P
R
\R
S
0
N
R
P
R
e
R C
A
0
C
e
η
N
R
N
R
N
R
e
=
P
R
\R
S
0
N
R
P
R
S
0
N
R
R
P
R
\R
e
R R
A
R
e
C C
e
η
N
R
N
R
N
R
e
=
P
R
\R
e
R
a
C
.
Finally, we observe that [(a e
P
R
\R
)
P
R
C
] =
[a
RC
], then W
V
= I
G
. Similarly, one can cal-
culate V
W
b
SC
. First we observe that [b
SC
] =
[(b e
P
+
S
\S
)
P
+
S
C
]. Then W
b
SC
= {(W
P
+
S
(b
e
N
+
P
+
S
\N
+
S
)}
N
+
P
+
S
C
, and
N
+
P
+
S
\N
+
S
S
0
P
+
S
N
+
P
+
S
e
N
+
S
P
+
S
\S
e
C
b
η
P
+
S S
=
N
+
P
+
S
\N
+
S
S
0
P
+
S
N
+
P
+
S
e
N
+
S
P
+
S
\S
e
C
B
C
e
η
P
+
S S S
e
=
N
+
P
+
S
\N
+
S
S
0
P
+
S
N
+
P
+
S
S
0
P
+
S
N
+
P
+
S
e
N
+
S
P
+
S
\S
C
B
C
e
P
+
S
e
η
P
+
S S S
P
+
S
e
=
N
+
P
+
S
\N
+
S
e
N
+
S
B
00
N
+
S
e
C C
e
η
P
+
S
e
,
where we used Eq. (97). Now, for V
W
[b
SC
] we
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 64
have
ψ
P
N
+
P
+
R
S
0
P
+
P
+
R
N
+
P
+
R
S
0
P
+
R
N
+
P
+
R
e
C
b
P
N
+
P
+
R
\N
+
P
+
R
e
R
P
+
P
+
R
P
+
P
+
R
e
η
P
+
R
P
+
R
\R
e
=
ψ
P
N
+
P
+
R
S
0
P
+
P
+
R
N
+
P
+
R
\N
+
R
e
N
+
R
B
00
N
+
R
e
C C
e
P
N
+
P
+
R
\N
+
P
+
R
e
P
+
P
+
R
P
+
P
+
R
e
=
C
b
R
P
+
P
+
R
\R
e
,
where Eq. (97) was used in the last step. The
arguments are straightforwardly generalised to
b [[
¯
A
(G)
S
¯
C]]
QR
.
F Proof of theorem 10
Proof. In the following, G
i
:
= (G, i) for i = 0, 1.
The argument in appendix E shows that
G
0
W
G
0
e
G
1
G
1
=
G
0
e
G
1
V
1
G
0
,
where (G, A, V
1
) is a GUR. Moreover, since
G
0
S
G
G
1
G
1
G
0
e
=
G
0
e
G
1
,
one has
G
0
e
G
1
=
G
0
W
1
G
0
W
G
0
e
G
1
G
1
G
1
=
G
0
S
G
G
1
W
G
1
S
G
G
0
e
G
1
G
0
G
0
G
1
V
1
G
1
=
G
0
S
G
G
1
W
G
1
V
1
G
0
G
1
G
0
G
0
e
,
namely
G
1
G
0
e
=
G
1
W
G
1
V
1
G
0
G
0
G
0
e
.
On the other hand, one can write the latter as
G
1
V
G
1
G
0
e
=
G
1
W
G
1
G
0
G
0
e
, (144)
or equivalently
G
0
e
G
1
V
G
1
=
G
0
W
1
G
0
e
G
1
G
1
.
Now, let us consider
G
0
˜
S
G
G
1
e
G
1
G
0
G
2
:
=
G
0
S
G
G
1
e
G
1
W
1
G
1
G
0
W
G
0
G
2
G
2
G
2
=
G
0
W
G
0
G
2
W
G
2
G
2
G
1
G
1
e
=
G
0
W
G
0
G
2
V
G
2
G
2
G
1
e
,
from which one concludes that
G
0
˜
S
G
G
1
e
G
1
G
0
=
G
1
e
G
0
X
G
0
,
for some X . Thus
G
0
W
G
0
G
2
V
G
2
G
2
=
G
0
X
G
0
G
2
.
Finally, this implies that W = X V
1
, and
in particular, by Eq. (144), it must be X = V ,
namely W = V V
1
. Consequently, we have
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 65
that
C
V
L
(A
R
)
C
G
0
G
0
G
1
=
C
A
R
C
G
0
W
1
G
0
G
0
W
G
0
G
1
G
1
G
1
=
C
A
R
C
G
0
V
1
G
0
G
0
V
G
0
G
1
,
and
G
0
G
1
V
+
L
(A
R
)
G
1
C C
=
G
0
W
1
G
0
W
G
0
G
1
G
1
A
R
G
1
G
1
C C
=
G
0
G
1
V
G
1
A
R
G
1
V
1
G
1
C C
.
G Proof of lemmas 66 and 67
We start with the proof of lemma 66.
Proof. (1) Notice that N
e
H
= φ(S
±
) = φ(N
±
e
G
).
Then |N
e
H
| |N
±
e
G
|, with strict inequality if and
only if φ(h
a
) = φ(h
b
) for some h
a
6= h
b
N
±
e
G
.
However, this is impossible because it would be
equivalent to φ(h
a
h
1
b
) R
0
, namely h
a
= h
b
,
contrarily to the hypothesis. Thus, |N
e
H
| =
|N
±
e
G
|. Invariance of neighbourhoods under left-
multiplication finally gives the thesis.
(2) Let now f P
e
H
= N
0∓
N
e
H
, namely there
exists h N
e
H
such that f N
0∓
h
, or equiva-
lently h N
f
. Then, f P
e
H
iff there exists
h N
e
H
N
f
. Equivalently, there exists h H
such that h = φ(h
a
) and h = fφ(h
b
), namely
f = φ(h
a
h
1
b
). Then P
e
H
= {φ(h
a
h
1
b
) | h
a
, h
b
N
±
e
G
}. By a similar argument, we have that
P
±
e
G
= {h
a
h
1
b
| h
a
, h
b
N
±
e
G
}. Consequently,
|P
e
H
| |{h
a
h
1
b
| h
a
, h
b
N
+
e
G
}| = |P
±
e
G
|. Now,
strict inequality in the last relation would require
that φ(h
a
h
1
b
) = φ(h
d
h
1
c
), contrarily to the hy-
pothesis. We conclude that |P
e
H
| = |P
±
e
G
|. Also
in this case the thesis can be obtained by invari-
ance of neighbourhoods under left-multiplication.
(3) Let N
f
1
N
f
2
= . Then clearly for every
g
i
φ
1
(f
i
) it must be N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
= . Let
then now h N
f
1
N
f
2
. This implies that
h = f
1
φ(h
a
) = f
2
φ(h
b
) for h
a
, h
b
N
±
e
G
. Conse-
quently, f
2
= f
1
φ(h
a
h
1
b
). Now, either f
1
= f
2
,
and then choosing g
1
= g
2
the thesis trivially fol-
lows, or φ(h
a
h
1
b
) 6∈ R
0
, and then h
a
h
1
b
6∈ R.
One can then set g
2
= g
1
h
a
h
1
b
, and verify that
g
2
φ
1
(f
2
), as well as k = g
1
h
a
= g
2
h
b
N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
. Thus, h = φ(k), and consequently
N
f
1
N
f
2
φ(N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
). This implies that
|N
f
1
N
f
2
| |N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
|, with a strict inequality
iff φ(k
1
) = φ(k
2
) for k
1
6= k
2
N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
. How-
ever, form the proof of item (1) we know that if
k
1
6= k
2
N
±
g
it must be φ(k
1
) 6= φ(k
2
). Thus,
|N
f
1
N
f
2
| = |φ(N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
)|, and N
f
1
N
f
2
=
φ(N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
).
(4) Let h P
0∓
f
2
N
f
1
. Then h = f
2
φ(h
1
c
h
b
) =
f
1
φ(h
a
), with h
a
, h
b
, h
c
N
±
e
G
. This implies
that f
2
= f
1
φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
). We can now set g
2
:
=
g
1
h
a
h
1
b
h
c
with g
1
φ
1
(f
1
). In this way,
one has f
2
= φ(g
2
). Let us set k
:
= g
1
h
a
=
g
2
h
1
c
h
b
P
g
2
N
±
g
1
. Then, h = φ(k), and
P
0∓
f
1
N
f
1
φ(P
g
2
N
±
g
1
). By the same argument
as for item (3), the thesis follows.
(5) Let h P
±
g
1
N
g
2
. Then h = g
1
h
a
h
1
b
, h =
g
2
h
1
c
, for some h
a
, h
b
, h
c
N
±
e
G
, and thus g
2
=
g
1
h
a
h
1
b
h
c
. On the other hand, by hypothesis,
for every h
x
N
±
e
G
one has g
2
6= g
1
h
x
. Collecting
all the informations, we have h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
x
6∈ R,
i.e. φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
x
) 6∈ R
0
, for every h
x
N
±
e
G
.
Then one has φ(g
2
) = φ(g
1
)φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
). By hy-
pothesis, it is also φ(g
2
) = φ(g
1
)φ(h
d
) for some
h
d
N
±
e
G
. This is clearly absurd, thus it must be
P
±
g
1
N
g
2
= .
Now, we provide the proof of lemma 67
Proof. (1) Let f
2
P
f
1
, namely f
2
=
f
1
φ(h
a
h
1
b
) for h
a
, h
b
N
±
e
G
. If f
1
= f
2
, it
is sufficient to choose g
1
= g
2
φ
1
(f
1
). Let
now f
1
6= f
2
. Then, let g
1
φ
1
(f
1
), and
g
2
:
= g
1
h
a
h
1
b
. By construction, φ(g
2
) = f
2
and
g
2
P
±
g
1
. Now, let h P
f
1
P
f
2
, namely h =
f
1
φ(h
f
h
1
e
) = f
2
φ(h
c
h
1
d
) = f
1
φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
).
Then we have φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
) R
0
, and
necessarily h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
R. This implies
that g
1
h
f
h
1
e
= g
1
h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
= g
2
h
c
h
1
d
. Now,
setting k
:
= g
1
h
f
h
1
e
, we have k = g
2
h
c
h
1
d
P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
, and h = φ(k). Thus, P
f
1
P
f
2
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 66
φ(P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
). Finally, by the same argument as
for the proof of item (2) of lemma 66, we get the
thesis.
(2) The hypothesis clearly implies that N
±
g
1
N
±
g
2
= . Suppose now that h P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
. Then
h = g
1
h
a
h
1
b
= g
2
h
d
h
1
c
for h
a
, h
b
, h
c
, h
d
N
±
e
G
.
This implies that g
2
= g
1
h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
, and con-
sequently φ(g
2
) = φ(g
1
)φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
). On the
other hand, we proved that for every h
e
, h
f
N
±
e
G
one has g
2
6= g
1
h
f
h
1
e
, while by hypothesis
φ(g
2
) = φ(g
1
)φ(h
f
h
1
e
) for some h
e
, h
f
N
±
e
G
.
Thus, while h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
6∈ R, it must be
φ(h
a
h
1
b
h
c
h
1
d
h
e
h
1
f
) 6∈ R
0
. We reached a con-
tradiction, and thus it must be P
±
g
1
P
±
g
2
= .
References
[1] Lucien Hardy. Disentangling nonlocality
and teleportation, 1999. arXiv:quant-ph/
9906123.
[2] Lucien Hardy. Quantum theory from five
reasonable axioms, 2001. arXiv:quant-ph/
0101012.
[3] Christopher A. Fuchs. Quantum mechanics
as quantum information (and only a little
more), 2002. arXiv:quant-ph/0205039.
[4] Gilles Brassard. Is information the key? Na-
ture Physics, 1(1):2–4, 2005. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1038/nphys134.
[5] Jonathan Barrett. Information processing in
generalized probabilistic theories. Phys. Rev.
A, 75:032304, Mar 2007. URL: https://
doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.75.032304.
[6] Giacomo M. D’Ariano. Probabilistic theo-
ries: What is special about quantum me-
chanics? In Alisa Bokulich and Gregg
Jaeger, editors, Philosophy of Quantum In-
formation and Entanglement, chapter 5,
pages 85–126. Cambridge University Press.,
2010. URL: https://doi.org/10.1017/
CBO9780511676550.007.
[7] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano and Alessandro
Tosini. Testing axioms for quantum the-
ory on probabilistic toy-theories. Quan-
tum Information Processing, 9(2):95–141,
2010. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11128-010-0172-3.
[8] Giulio Chiribella, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
and Paolo Perinotti. Probabilistic theories
with purification. Phys. Rev. A, 81:062348,
Jun 2010. URL: https://doi.org/10.
1103/PhysRevA.81.062348.
[9] Giulio Chiribella, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
and Paolo Perinotti. Informational deriva-
tion of quantum theory. Phys. Rev. A,
84:012311, Jul 2011. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1103/PhysRevA.84.012311.
[10] Lluís Masanes and Markus P Müller. A
derivation of quantum theory from physi-
cal requirements. New Journal of Physics,
13(6):063001, jun 2011. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1088/1367-2630/13/6/063001.
[11] Borivoje Dakić and Časlav Brukner. Quan-
tum theory and beyond: is entangle-
ment special? In H. Halvorson, edi-
tor, Deep Beauty: Understanding the Quan-
tum World through Mathematical Innova-
tion, pages 365–392. Cambridge University
Press, 2011. URL: https://doi.org/10.
1017/CBO9780511976971.011.
[12] Peter Rastall. Locality, Bell’s theorem,
and quantum mechanics. Foundations of
Physics, 15(9):963–972, Sep 1985. URL:
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00739036.
[13] Sandu Popescu and Daniel Rohrlich. Quan-
tum nonlocality as an axiom. Foundations
of Physics, 24(3):379–385, Mar 1994. URL:
https://doi.org/10.1007/BF02058098.
[14] Robert W. Spekkens. Evidence for the
epistemic view of quantum states: A toy
theory. Phys. Rev. A, 75:032110, Mar
2007. URL: https://doi.org/10.1103/
PhysRevA.75.032110.
[15] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano, Giulio Chiri-
bella, and Paolo Perinotti. Quantum the-
ory from first principles: an informational
approach. Cambridge University Press,
2017. URL: https://doi.org/10.1017/
9781107338340.
[16] Howard Barnum, Jonathan Barrett,
Matthew Leifer, and Alexander Wilce. Tele-
portation in general probabilistic theories,
2008. arXiv:0805.3553.
[17] Howard Barnum and Alexander Wilce.
Information processing in convex oper-
ational theories. Electronic Notes in
Theoretical Computer Science, 270(1):3
15, 2011. Proceedings of the Joint
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 67
5th International Workshop on Quantum
Physics and Logic and 4th Workshop on
Developments in Computational Models
(QPL/DCM 2008). URL: https://doi.
org/10.1016/j.entcs.2011.01.002.
[18] Bob Coecke. Kindergarten quantum me-
chanics: Lecture notes. AIP Conference Pro-
ceedings, 810(1):81–98, 2006. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1063/1.2158713.
[19] Bob Coecke and Aleks Kissinger. Pictur-
ing Quantum Processes: A First Course
in Quantum Theory and Diagrammatic
Reasoning. Cambridge University Press,
2017. URL: https://doi.org/10.1017/
9781316219317.
[20] Günther Ludwig. Foundations of quan-
tum mechanics II. New York, NY (United
States); Springer-Verlag, 1985. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-28726-2.
[21] Alexander Wilce. Test spaces and orthoal-
gebras. In Bob Coecke, David Moore,
and Alexander Wilce, editors, Current
Research in Operational Quantum Logic:
Algebras, Categories, Languages, pages
81–114. Springer Netherlands, Dordrecht,
2000. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
978-94-017-1201-9_4.
[22] Michael A. Nielsen and Isaac L. Chuang.
Quantum Computation and Quantum Infor-
mation: 10th Anniversary Edition. Cam-
bridge University Press, 2010. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511976667.
[23] Alessandro Bisio, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
and Alessandro Tosini. Dirac quantum cel-
lular automaton in one dimension: Zit-
terbewegung and scattering from poten-
tial. Phys. Rev. A, 88:032301, Sep
2013. URL: https://doi.org/10.1103/
PhysRevA.88.032301.
[24] Alessandro Bisio, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
and Alessandro Tosini. Quantum field as
a quantum cellular automaton: The dirac
free evolution in one dimension. Annals of
Physics, 354:244 264, 2015. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1016/j.aop.2014.12.016.
[25] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano and Paolo
Perinotti. Derivation of the dirac equation
from principles of information processing.
Phys. Rev. A, 90:062106, Dec 2014. URL:
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.90.
062106.
[26] Alessandro Bisio, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
Paolo Perinotti, and Alessandro Tosini.
Weyl, Dirac and Maxwell quantum cel-
lular automata. Foundations of Physics,
45(10):1203–1221, Oct 2015. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1007/s10701-015-9927-0.
[27] Richard P. Feynman. Simulating physics
with computers. International Jour-
nal of Theoretical Physics, 21(6):467–488,
1982. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
BF02650179.
[28] Wim van Dam. Quantum Cellular Au-
tomata. PhD thesis, University of Nijmegen,
1996. URL: https://sites.cs.ucsb.edu/
~vandam/qca.pdf.
[29] J. Watrous. On one-dimensional quantum
cellular automata. In Proceedings of IEEE
36th Annual Foundations of Computer Sci-
ence, pages 528–537, Oct 1995. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1109/SFCS.1995.492583.
[30] J Gruska. Quantum Computing. McGraw-
Hill, 1999.
[31] B. Schumacher and R. F. Werner. Reversible
quantum cellular automata, 2004. arXiv:
quant-ph/0405174.
[32] Pablo Arrighi, Vincent Nesme, and Rein-
hard Werner. Unitarity plus causality im-
plies localizability. Journal of Computer
and System Sciences, 77(2):372 378, 2011.
Adaptivity in Heterogeneous Environments.
URL: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jcss.
2010.05.004.
[33] D. Gross, V. Nesme, H. Vogts, and R. F.
Werner. Index theory of one dimen-
sional quantum walks and cellular automata.
Communications in Mathematical Physics,
310(2):419–454, Mar 2012. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1007/s00220-012-1423-1.
[34] Pablo Arrighi, Renan Fargetton, Vincent
Nesme, and Eric Thierry. Applying causal-
ity principles to the axiomatization of prob-
abilistic cellular automata. In Benedikt
Löwe, Dag Normann, Ivan Soskov, and
Alexandra Soskova, editors, Models of Com-
putation in Context, pages 1–10, Berlin,
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 68
Heidelberg, 2011. Springer Berlin Heidel-
berg. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
978-3-642-21875-0_1.
[35] Sergey B. Bravyi and Alexei Yu. Ki-
taev. Fermionic quantum computation.
Annals of Physics, 298(1):210 226,
2002. URL: https://doi.org/10.1006/
aphy.2002.6254.
[36] G. M. D’Ariano, F. Manessi, P. Perinotti,
and A. Tosini. Fermionic computa-
tion is non-local tomographic and vio-
lates monogamy of entanglement. EPL
(Europhysics Letters), 107(2):20009, jul
2014. URL: https://doi.org/10.1209/
0295-5075/107/20009.
[37] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano, Franco Manessi,
Paolo Perinotti, and Alessandro Tosini. The
feynman problem and fermionic entangle-
ment: Fermionic theory versus qubit theory.
International Journal of Modern Physics A,
29(17):1430025, 2014. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1142/S0217751X14300257.
[38] Y. Aharonov, L. Davidovich, and N. Za-
gury. Quantum random walks. Phys. Rev.
A, 48:1687–1690, Aug 1993. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.48.1687.
[39] Dorit Aharonov, Andris Ambainis, Julia
Kempe, and Umesh Vazirani. Quantum
walks on graphs. In Proceedings of the
Thirty-Third Annual ACM Symposium on
Theory of Computing, STOC ’01, pages 50–
59, New York, NY, USA, 2001. Association
for Computing Machinery. URL: https:
//doi.org/10.1145/380752.380758.
[40] Peter L. Knight, Eugenio Roldán, and J. E.
Sipe. Propagating quantum walks: The
origin of interference structures. Jour-
nal of Modern Optics, 51(12):1761–1777,
2004. URL: https://doi.org/10.1080/
09500340408232489.
[41] Norio Konno. A new type of limit theo-
rems for the one-dimensional quantum ran-
dom walk. J. Math. Soc. Japan, 57(4):1179–
1195, 10 2005. URL: https://doi.org/10.
2969/jmsj/1150287309.
[42] Hilary A Carteret, Mourad E H Ismail, and
Bruce Richmond. Three routes to the exact
asymptotics for the one-dimensional quan-
tum walk. Journal of Physics A: Mathe-
matical and General, 36(33):8775–8795, aug
2003. URL: https://doi.org/10.1088/
0305-4470/36/33/305.
[43] Andris Ambainis, Eric Bach, Ashwin Nayak,
Ashvin Vishwanath, and John Watrous.
One-dimensional quantum walks. In Pro-
ceedings of the Thirty-Third Annual ACM
Symposium on Theory of Computing, STOC
’01, pages 37–49, New York, NY, USA,
2001. Association for Computing Machinery.
URL: https://doi.org/10.1145/380752.
380757.
[44] Alessandro Bisio, Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano,
Paolo Perinotti, and Alessandro Tosini.
Thirring quantum cellular automaton.
Phys. Rev. A, 97:032132, Mar 2018. URL:
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.97.
032132.
[45] Paolo Perinotti and Leopoldo Poggiali.
Scalar fermionic cellular automata on finite
cayley graphs. Phys. Rev. A, 98:052337, Nov
2018. URL: https://doi.org/10.1103/
PhysRevA.98.052337.
[46] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano and Paolo
Perinotti. Quantum cellular automata
and free quantum field theory. Fron-
tiers of Physics, 12(1):120301, Sep
2016. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11467-016-0616-z.
[47] P. de la Harpe. Topics in Geometric
Group Theory. Chicago Lectures in Math-
ematics. University of Chicago Press, 2000.
URL: https://press.uchicago.edu/ucp/
books/book/chicago/T/bo3641370.html.
[48] Shuichi Inokuchi and Yoshihiro Mizoguchi.
Generalized partitioned quantum cellular
automata and quantization of classical ca.
Int. Journ. of Unconventional Comput-
ing, 1:149–160, 2005. arXiv:quant-ph/
0312102.
[49] J. von Neumann. On infinite direct
products. Compositio Mathematica, 6:1–
77, 1939. URL: http://www.numdam.org/
item/CM_1939__6__1_0.
[50] F. J. Murray and J. v. Neumann. On
rings of operators. Annals of Mathematics,
37(1):116–229, 1936. URL: https://doi.
org/10.2307/1968693.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 69
[51] Rainer J. Nagel. Order unit and base norm
spaces. In A. Hartkämper and H. Neumann,
editors, Foundations of Quantum Mechan-
ics and Ordered Linear Spaces: Advanced
Study Institute Marburg 1973, pages 23–29.
Springer Berlin Heidelberg, Berlin, Heidel-
berg, 1974. URL: https://doi.org/10.
1007/3-540-06725-6_4.
[52] David Beckman, Daniel Gottesman, M. A.
Nielsen, and John Preskill. Causal and lo-
calizable quantum operations. Phys. Rev. A,
64:052309, Oct 2001. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1103/PhysRevA.64.052309.
[53] T Eggeling, D Schlingemann, and R. F
Werner. Semicausal operations are semilo-
calizable. Europhysics Letters (EPL),
57(6):782–788, mar 2002. URL: https://
doi.org/10.1209/epl/i2002-00579-4.
[54] Benjamin Schumacher and Michael D. West-
moreland. Locality and information trans-
fer in quantum operations. Quantum In-
formation Processing, 4(1):13–34, February
2005. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
s11128-004-3193-y.
[55] Jonathan Barrett, Robin Lorenz, and
Ognyan Oreshkov. Quantum causal models.
2019. arXiv:1906.10726.
[56] Pablo Arrighi, Nicolas Schabanel, and Guil-
laume Theyssier. Stochastic cellular au-
tomata: Correlations, decidability and simu-
lations. Fundamenta Informaticae, 126:121–
156, 2013. URL: https://doi.org/10.
3233/FI-2013-875.
[57] Giacomo Mauro D’Ariano, Marco Erba, and
Paolo Perinotti. Isotropic quantum walks on
lattices and the weyl equation. Phys. Rev. A,
96:062101, Dec 2017. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1103/PhysRevA.96.062101.
[58] Lucien Hardy and William K. Wootters.
Limited holism and real-vector-space quan-
tum theory. Foundations of Physics,
42(3):454–473, 2012. URL: https://doi.
org/10.1007/s10701-011-9616-6.
[59] Karl-Peter Hadeler and Johannes Müller.
Introduction. In Cellular Automata:
Analysis and Applications, pages 1–17.
Springer International Publishing, Cham,
2017. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
978-3-319-53043-7_1.
[60] Pablo Arrighi and Vincent Nesme. The
block neighborhood. In Jarkko Kari, ed-
itor, Second Symposium on Cellular Au-
tomata Journeés Automates Cellulaires”,
JAC 2010, Turku, Finland, December
15-17, 2010. Proceedings, pages 43–53.
Turku Center for Computer Science, 2010.
URL: https://hal.archives-ouvertes.
fr/hal-00542488.
[61] Pablo Arrighi, Vincent Nesme, and Rein-
hard F. Werner. Bounds on the speedup in
quantum signaling. Phys. Rev. A, 95:012331,
Jan 2017. URL: https://doi.org/10.
1103/PhysRevA.95.012331.
[62] Michael Freedman and Matthew B. Hast-
ings. Classification of quantum cel-
lular automata. Communications in
Mathematical Physics, 376(2):1171–1222,
2020. URL: https://doi.org/10.1007/
s00220-020-03735-y.
[63] Michael Freedman, Jeongwan Haah, and
Matthew B Hastings. The group structure
of quantum cellular automata. 2019. arXiv:
1910.07998.
[64] Terry Farrelly. A review of quantum cellular
automata, 2019. arXiv:1904.13318.
[65] P. Arrighi. An overview of quantum cellular
automata. Natural Computing, 18(4):885–
899, 2019. URL: https://doi.org/10.
1007/s11047-019-09762-6.
[66] Alessandro Bisio, Giacomo D’Ariano, Nicola
Mosco, Paolo Perinotti, and Alessandro
Tosini. Solutions of a two-particle interact-
ing quantum walk. Entropy, 20(6):435, Jun
2018. URL: https://doi.org/10.3390/
e20060435.
Accepted in Quantum 2020-07-03, click title to verify. Published under CC-BY 4.0. 70